• No results found

Introduction: the role of the exemplar in Arendt and Spinoza : Insights for moral exemplarism and moral education

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "Introduction: the role of the exemplar in Arendt and Spinoza : Insights for moral exemplarism and moral education"

Copied!
10
0
0

Loading.... (view fulltext now)

Full text

(1)

Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at

https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=ceae20

Ethics and Education

ISSN: 1744-9642 (Print) 1744-9650 (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/ceae20

Introduction: the role of the exemplar in Arendt

and Spinoza: insights for moral exemplarism and

moral education

Johan Dahlbeck & Morten Timmermann Korsgaard

To cite this article: Johan Dahlbeck & Morten Timmermann Korsgaard (2020): Introduction: the role of the exemplar in Arendt and Spinoza: insights for moral exemplarism and moral education, Ethics and Education, DOI: 10.1080/17449642.2020.1731173

To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/17449642.2020.1731173

© 2020 The Author(s). Published by Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis Group.

Published online: 17 Feb 2020.

Submit your article to this journal

Article views: 35

View related articles

(2)

ARTICLE

Introduction: the role of the exemplar in Arendt and Spinoza:

insights for moral exemplarism and moral education

Johan Dahlbeck and Morten Timmermann Korsgaard

Faculty of Education and Society, Malmö University, Malmö, Sweden

ABSTRACT

In late October of 2019, we brought together scholars from very different traditions in order to explore the notion of exemplarity and the role of exemplars in education. Bringing together scho-lars working on ethics and moral exemplarism, Spinoza schoscho-lars and Arendt scholars, we attempted to bring these different perspectives to bear on the role of exemplarity in education. Not in order to create a synthesis of ideas or tofind solutions for practical issues, but in order to explore collegially the important issue of exemplarity in education. On the one hand, it was an attempt to put something on the table, and on the other, it was an attempt to bring people together in order to share a couple of days away from everyday academic life so as to engage the object of study without distractions. Part of what it occasioned can be read in this special issue.

KEYWORDS

Exemplarism; Arendt; Spinoza

“Can you feel the warmth of the Hive?”

Tom in Leave No Trace (2018).

In a haunting scene in the motion picture Leave No Trace1(Granik2018), Tom, an adolescent girl living on the edges of normality, teaches her father about the miraculous workings of a beehive, symbolically asking if he can feel the warmth of the hive. In this scene, portraying the pedagogical triangle of teacher, object, and student, the father is taught not only about the wonders of bees and their habitat, but also a lesson about the benefits of commonality and solidarity. The daughter tells the father– who is suffering from PTSD and craves only solitude – not to be afraid of the bees, as he extends his bare hands to the hive. In this symbolic gesture, the daughter is also telling him to extend his hands to others and to feel the warmth of living together with others. The daughter inadver-tently uses the hive as a way of exemplifying to her father the value of commu-nity. She is teaching him more than the example is intended to exemplify. In her work on exemplarity, Harvey (2002) has shown how examples always carry with them more than simply pointing to something general through the particular.

CONTACTJohan Dahlbeck johan.dahlbeck@mah.se Faculty of Education and Society, Malmö University, Malmö, Sweden

https://doi.org/10.1080/17449642.2020.1731173

© 2020 The Author(s). Published by Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis Group.

This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/), which permits non-commercial re-use, distribution, and reproduc-tion in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited, and is not altered, transformed, or built upon in any way.

(3)

Examples are symbolic signifiers as much as they are simple instantiations of general rules.

In late October of 2019, we brought together scholars from very different traditions in order to explore the notion of exemplarity and the role of exem-plars in education. Bringing together scholars working on ethics and moral exemplarism, Spinoza scholars and Arendt scholars, we attempted to bring these different perspectives to bear on the role of exemplarity in education. Not in order to create a synthesis of ideas or tofind solutions for practical issues, but in order to explore collegially the important issue of exemplarity in educa-tion. On the one hand, it was an attempt to‘put something on the table’ thus offering it up for collective study, and on the other, it was an attempt to bring people together in order to share a couple of days away from everyday aca-demic life so as to make it possible to engage the object of study without distractions. Part of what it occasioned can be read in this special issue. However, the value of the colloquium was just as much the feeling of collegiality and community that developed during the two intense days. This warmth of the hive can unfortunately not be rendered in this format, but perhaps the papers speak in some measure at least of the ideas and thoughts that were exchanged during the colloquium.

Moral exemplarism is emerging as a prominent ethical theory answering to practical challenges within both politics and education. Largely due to its heritage from classical Aristotelianism, exemplarism highlights the ancient notion of emu-lation as a crucial component of social and moral life. Emuemu-lation, however, is not the only way in which exemplars can function in moral judgement and education. Here, the insights of Arendt and Spinoza represent neglected perspectives cap-able of broadening the understanding of the exemplar in education. While Arendt’s theory of judgement offers a nuanced account of how we employ exemplars in judgement, via her concept of enlarged thinking, Spinoza’s political psychology promises to further enable the use of exemplars as means of both political and personal deliberation by highlighting the interconnectedness of human sociability and the improvement of the understanding.

As different as they are, both Arendt and Spinoza are frequently acknowl-edged as key figures in the development of modern ethical, political, and educational reflection. Yet, to limit ourselves to a narrow historical evaluation of their contribution would amount to missing out on a major source of insight for rethinking today’s ethical, political, and educational concerns. While estab-lished scholars of Arendt and Spinoza have utilized their methods and ideas to illuminate contemporary problems, this discussion deserves both greater atten-tion and continued development so as to facilitate the further exploraatten-tion of the implications of exemplarism for contemporary moral education.

To this end, the colloquium served to facilitate a critical dialogue in order to promote a reappraisal of Arendt’s and Spinoza’s ideas concerning the role of the exemplar and of their relevance for contemporary educational inquiry and for

(4)

the development of exemplarism as a moral and educational concept. Specifically, the three plenary discussions aimed to provide a forum for critical discussion where the invited plenary speakers and discussants engaged with questions from the participants of the colloquium.

The concept of exemplarity is receiving increasing attention in contemporary education. In times of increasing unrest and uncertainty due to international conflicts, climate change, and political upheaval, education is frequently con-ceived as a sphere for enhancing security and future participation in political life. Education, it is believed, can play a part in developing morally conscious citizens and in securing the future survival of democracy. These thoughts connote an instrumental approach to education, where ethical theories and philosophy are tasked with‘fixing’ immediate political problems. In this collo-quium, we wanted to approach the role of exemplars in education from a different, more educationally attuned, vantage point. This meant engaging the idea of exemplars as an object of study, and not as a means for primarily improving educational processes orfixing societal issues. Engaging with three distinct perspectives and theories on exemplarity - moral exemplarism, Spinoza, and Arendt - permitted us to highlight central aspects of how we can think of exemplars educationally and how these may function in educational processes. In the following we will briefly outline the three perspectives in order to set the scene for the different contributions to this special issue.

In moral education theory, exemplarism is increasingly gaining popularity, to the point that something like an exemplarist approach is arising among Aristotelian education scholars (Croce and Vaccarezza 2017; Kristjánsson 2006; Sanderse2013). However, it is the ethical theory of exemplarism as formulated by Linda Zagzebski, which presents the most comprehensive attempt at formulating a philosophical foundation for exemplarist moral education (Zagzebski 2010,

2015,2017). Zagzebski outlines the philosophical framework of exemplarism as a theory facilitating the practical study of exemplars as a motivational force for moral education and self-improvement. Being deeply rooted in classical virtue ethics, exemplarism focuses on how the emotion of admiration can be employed to engage the imagination so that stories of human exemplars can enrich ideas about the good and virtuous life. Zagzebski suggests that, above all, it is the practical utility of exemplarism that sets it apart from other competing moral theories. The practical utility of exemplarism is also what connects it with educa-tion as educaeduca-tion is frequently conceived as the social arena par excellence for fostering young people through the use of exemplars.

Zagzebski attempts to formulate a theory that can both describe the basis for moral judgement and guide us in making particular moral judgements. Zagzebski uses the term ‘hook’ to describe the link between a moral theory and a moral practice (Zagzebski2017, 8). The exemplar functions as a guiding rod for moral action, and we acquire moral virtue by admiring and attempting to imitate the admirable exemplar. Exemplarity thus founds the theory as both

(5)

theory and practice. The basis for her claim is the theory of direct reference as proposed by Hillary Putnam and Saul Kripke in the 1970s. The theory of direct reference states that we can refer to objects by direct reference without needing description (Zagzebski2013, 198–199). We can thus refer to objects by claiming that they are objects like that, without needing further knowledge about them, or needing observation nor description. Zagzebski uses the examples of water and gold to illustrate this point. We do not need to know that water is H2O in order to refer to and understand what is being referred to when we use the word water. The same goes for gold, and in fact, for many centuries we did not know the deeper structures of gold and water, but referred to them and under-stood what we meant by the words nonetheless. In the same way, exemplars– through direct reference – allow us to identify moral goodness in various instantiations of it, and such practices are already embedded in our moral practice (Zagzebski2013, 199–200). Description or empirical studies can confirm or negate our assumption, but that does not preclude us from usingfigures as examples of moral goodness, and it does not preclude us from learning from them. That they are seen as admirable affords us the opportunity to imitate moral goodness.

While the admiration-imitation model is highly relevant for contemporary education, and for working with values and moral education, there is a dimension missing from the theory. This concerns how exemplars function when they are not based on admiration and emulation, but instead function as leading strings (Kant 1965, 178) for judging. This way of engaging the role of examples and exemplars has been explored by Hannah Arendt in her work on judgement, which draws specifically from the work of Kant (Arendt1992,1998,

2006; Beiner1994,1997; DeCaroli2007; Korsgaard2018). However, the specific role of exemplarism in her theory of judgement remains under-explored. This in spite of the fact that over the past decades Hannah Arendt has received increasing attention in various areas of educational research, such as educa-tional theory, philosophy of education, educaeduca-tional leadership, philosophy for children, and inclusive education (Biesta2006,2010; Gordon2001; Gunter2013; Harwood2010; Hayden2012; Higgins2011; Korsgaard2016,2018; Masschelein

2011; Levinson1997; Vansieleghem2005). According to Arendt, our ability to judge right and wrong hinges on our ability to‘go visiting’ the perspectives of exemplary others, something Arendt, following Kant, coins enlarged thinking. In other words, our ability to judge depends upon the company– fictitious or real, past or present– we choose (Arendt2003, 145–146). This is not an admiration-emulation model of exemplarism, but rather a way of conceiving the role of exemplars in our thinking about and judging in particular situations. The colloquium providing the basis for this special issue explored how Arendt’s use of exemplars in formulating a theory of judgement – in critical dialogue with the work of Spinoza– can help to elucidate some of the underdeveloped aspects of exemplarism in Zagzebski’s theory of moral exemplarism.

(6)

Spinoza’s employment of the exemplar is well documented and debated in contemporary Spinoza scholarship (see e.g. Rosenthal2002; Gatens2009,2012; Steinberg 2018a). Recent developments in the field have seen an increasing interest in the strong link between Spinoza’s ethical theory (formulated in relation to his metaphysics in the Ethics) and his political philosophy (laid out in his Theological-Political Treatise and in his unfinished Political Treatise) (see e.g. James2010,2012; Steinberg2014,2018a,2018b). Focusing on the link between ethics and politics has involved elucidating the curious connection between Spinoza’s naturalistic psychology and his political philosophy in ways that indicate how the means for striving for individual eudaimonia in many ways parallel, and are constrained by, the means for establishing political stability and collective flourishing (Gatens & Lloyd,1999; Steinberg2018b). This involves investigating how the imagination can be productively employed via narratives so as to create a cognitive bridge between a largely inadequate understanding of the world and a– relatively speaking – more adequate understanding, necessary for maintaining both political stability and promoting individual well-being (Gatens2009,2012). Part of this means reevaluating the roles of desire, passion and the imagination in the context of Spinoza’s political philosophy in a way that involves what Heidi M. Ravven (1990) has called‘the education of desire’ and Justin Steinberg an ‘affec-tive reorientation’ (2018b, 100). Put more broadly, this means shifting the under-standing of Spinoza’s political philosophy from a kind of classical liberalism to a particularism couched in a perfectionist framework.

In his political texts, Spinoza makes use of exemplars borrowed from Scripture, explaining how a given political context– such as that of the Hebrew state – can be manipulated through narratives (such as Moses guiding the Israelites by way of prophecy) in a way that illustrates the power of the exemplar as a tool for political governance (Rosenthal2002). While Spinoza’s political texts appear to highlight aspects concerned more with the tempering of dangerous passive affects, his ethical theory also places focus on the positive aspects of using exemplars. In the Ethics, Spinoza introduces the exemplar of the free man as a cognitive tool for imagining and striving for moral perfectionism in a way that is highly sensitive to the particularities of historical and geographical contexts. The exemplar of the free man evokes connotations of a deeply educational nature, where the education of the individual is bound up with the formation of the collective imagination, and where theflourishing of the individual and the flourishing of the community are both conceived to hinge on the relative improvement of the understanding (Gatens and Lloyd1999). While the educational implications of Spinoza’s moral philosophy has been the focus of recent scholarship in educational theory (see e.g. Dahlbeck2016, 2018), the promise of his version of moral exemplarism for moral education offers an exciting and under-explored aspect of Spinoza’s philo-sophy that this special issue seeks to address.

The colloquium offered us a unique opportunity to come together from different fields and traditions and jointly explore a central philosophical concept

(7)

in relation to a practical problem: that of moral education. In the contributions to the colloquium wefind very different ways of approaching the issue and different traditions of thought being exercised. In the first contribution Maria Silvia Vaccarezza outlines three ancient paths toflourishing via imitation of exemplary individuals: The Platonic, the Stoic, and the Aristotelian. Endeavouring to reconcile these models practically, Vaccarezza proposes a multi-step educational program incorporating different models and eliciting different sorts of admiration and imitation in the novice. In the second contribution, Justin Steinberg turns to the Renaissance humanist rhetorical approaches to pedagogy of Juan Vives in order to argue that Spinoza’s political theory can give us a model for how he might have approached a treatise on moral education. Illustrating how Spinoza joins Vives’ humanist understanding of ingenium (character) with a Hobbesian scientific approach, Steinberg suggests that Spinoza offers us a pedagogical model in the guise of a political method that is in part science, in part art. The third contribution by Steven DeCaroli narrows in on the concept of crisis in Arendt’s work. DeCaroli draws a connection between judgement and crisis, linking it to the work of the classroom. The relationship between crisis and judgement in Arendt is examined in connection to Immanuel Kant and Adolf Eichmann, twofigures who DeCaroli argues embody opposing aspects of what it means to judge, epitomized by a conceptual tension between example and cliché. In the fourth contribution, Michel Croce proposes a liberal account of moral exemplarism, challenging two key assumptions of Linda Zagzebski’s exemplarist moral theory – that moral exemplars are exceptionally virtuous agents and that imitating their behavior is the main strategy for acquiring the virtues. Croce discusses the notions of enkratic exemplars and injustice illuminators, arguing that there are good reasons for considering them moral exemplars although they fail to satisfy (either of) the key assumptions. In the fifth contribution, Moira Gatens explores Spinoza’s notions of singularity, similarity, and exemplarity in relation to the distinctive human capacity to educate the senses and the passions and to cultivate reason, and thereby toflourish. Building on this exploration, Gatens goes on to read the education of Victor Frankenstein’s ‘monster’ (in Shelley’s novel) through the lens of Spinoza’s philosophy of affect. The sixth contribution, by David Lewin, con-tinues to explore the relationship between narrativefictions and moral education by considering some philosophical issues concerning the influence of folk and fairy tales on moral development. Lewin discusses issues of representation and reduction, drawing on a distinction between a problematic reductionism and an appropriate pedagogical reduction, suggesting that pedagogical issues of repre-sentation require us to think about how to represent complexity in ways that are reductive without being reductionist, that can delight and engage without being horrifying or tedious. The seventh contribution by Heidi M. Ravven returns us to the exemplarism of Spinoza. Ravven suggests that Spinoza attributes to society the role of moral educator, a role that is to be carried out via Religion and Politics and hence also via an educational system. Ravven argues that, for Spinoza, while

(8)

intellectual virtue is exposed as the necessary and only true fulfillment of the virtue of moral models, it is not ready to hand but must be taught. Because teaching necessarily entails an initial measure of authoritative transmission and even coercion, Ravven suggests that moral models must be internalized. In the penultimate contribution, Morten T. Korsgaard explores the significance of exem-plarity for Hannah Arendt’s theory of judgement. Via the metaphor of going visiting, the paper explores how judgement for Arendt does not concern deter-mination of what to do, but rather concerns widening one’s understanding and reconciling oneself to the world. Thefinal contribution by Johan Dahlbeck and Moa De Lucia Dahlbeck offers a reading of Spinoza as moral exemplarist where his political theory suggests that instead of constructing his exemplar on the idea of a supremely moral person, Spinoza emphasizes the concept of ingenium in order to chisel out an imperfect model of human behavior. The authors argue that the purpose for this is to avoid a utopian and inefficient political theory and to work out a moral practice that is capable of assisting people and communities in ethical self-transformation.

Note

1. In thefilm, a father suffering from PTSD and his daughter are searching for a place to live their life in peace. The father craves solitude and is unable to live up to the requirements of society, and the daughter is increasingly longing for company and belonging. Being ousted from their secluded forest habitat, after being spotted by a jogger, the pairfind themselves in and amongst ‘normal’ life. At first the father tries to find his feet, but being unable to stand the stress of being around people the pair once again escape into the woods. After an accidental fall, the father receives treatment in a small community also living‘outside’ of regular society. Here the daughter finds the community and solidarity she has been craving, while the father continues to struggle.

Disclosure statement

No potential conflict of interest was reported by the authors.

Funding

This work was supported by the Riksbankens Jubileumsfond [Dnr F19-1018:1].

ORCID

Johan Dahlbeck http://orcid.org/0000-0003-1669-7132

(9)

References

Arendt, H.1992. Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy, ed R. Beiner. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Arendt, H.1998. The Human Condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Arendt, H.2003. Responsibility and Judgment. New York: Random House. Arendt, H.2006. Between past and Future. London: Penguin Books.

Beiner, R.1994.“Judging in a World of Appearances.” In Hannah Arendt: Critical Essays, edited by L. P. Hinchman and S. K. Hinchman, 365–387. Albany: State University of New York Press. Beiner, R.1997.“Rereading Hannah Arendt S Kant Lectures.” Philosophy Social Criticism 23 (1):

21–32. doi:10.1177/019145379702300102.

Biesta, G. J. J.2006. Beyond Learning: Democratic Education for a Human Future. Boulder, CO: Paradigm Publishers.

Biesta, G. J. J.2010. Good Education in an Age of Measurement: Ethics, Politics, Democracy. Boulder, CO: Paradigm Publishers.

Croce, M., and M. S. Vaccarezza.2017.“Educating through Exemplars: Alternative Paths to Virtue.” Theory and Research in Education. doi:10.1177/1477878517695903.

Dahlbeck, J. 2016. Spinoza and Education: Freedom, Understanding and Empowerment. London: Routledge.

Dahlbeck, J.2018. Education and Free Will: Spinoza, Causal Determinism and Moral Formation. London: Routledge.

DeCaroli, S. 2007. “A Capacity for Agreement: Hannah Arendt and the “Critique of Judgment”.” Social Theory and Practice 33 (3): 361–386. Stable URLhttps://www.jstor.org/ stable/23558481

Gatens, M. 2009. “Spinoza’s Disturbing Thesis: Power, Norms and Fiction in the Tractatus Theologico-Politicus.” History of Political Thought 30 (1): 455–468.

Gatens, M.2012.“Compelling Fictions: Spinoza and George Eliot on Imagination and Belief.” European Journal of Philosophy 20 (1): 74–90. doi:10.1111/ejop.2012.20.issue-1.

Gatens, M., and G. Lloyd. 1999. Collective Imaginings: Spinoza, past and Present. London: Routledge.

Gordon, M., ed.2001. Hannah Arendt and Education: Renewing Our Common World. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

Granik, D. dir.2018. Leave No Trace. New York: Bleecker Street.

Gunter, H. M.2013. Educational Leadership and Hannah Arendt. London: Routledge.

Harvey, I.2002. Labyrinths of Exemplarity: At the Limits of Deconstruction. New York: SUNY Press.

Harwood, V.2010.“The Place of Imagination in Inclusive Pedagogy: Thinking with Maxine Greene and Hannah Arendt.” International Journal of Inclusive Education 14 (4): 357–369. doi:10.1080/13603110802504572.

Hayden, M. J.2012.“Arendt and Cosmopolitanism: The Human Conditions of Cosmopolitan Teacher Education.” Ethics and Global Politics 5 (4): 239–258. Stable URLhttp://www. ethicsandglobalpolitics.net/index.php/egp/article/view/20271

Higgins, C.2011. The Good Life of Teaching: An Ethics of Professional Practice. Malden MA: Wiley- Blackwell.

James, S.2010.“Narrative as the Means to Freedom: Spinoza on the Uses of Imagination.” In Spinoza’s ‘Theological-Political Treatise’: A Critical Guide, edited by Y. Y. Melamed and M. A. Rosenthal, 250–267. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

James, S.2012. Spinoza on Philosophy, Religion, and Politics: The Theologico-Political Treatise. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Kant, I.1965. Critique of Pure Reason, translated by N. K. Smith. New York: St. Martin s Press. 8 J. DAHLBECK AND M. T. KORSGAARD

(10)

Korsgaard, M. T. 2016. “An Arendtian Perspective on Inclusive Education: Towards a Reimagined Vocabulary.” International Journal of Inclusive Education 20 (9): 934–945. doi:10.1080/13603116.2015.1130180.

Korsgaard, M. T.2018. Bearing with Strangers. Arendt, Education and the Politics of Inclusion. London: Routledge.

Kristjánsson, K.2006.“’emulation and the Use of Role Models in Moral Education’.” Journal of Moral Education 35 (1): 37–49. doi:10.1080/03057240500495278.

Levinson, N.1997.“Teaching in the Midst of Belatedness: The Paradox of Natality in Hannah Arendt S Educational Thought.” Educational Theory 47 (4): 435–451. doi: 10.1111/j.1741-5446.1997.00435.x.

Masschelein, J.2011.“Experimentum Scholae: The World Once More . . . But Not (Yet) Finished.” Studies in Philosophy and Education 30: 529–535. doi:10.1007/978-94-007-4017-4_15. Ravven, H. M. 1990. “Spinoza’s Materialist Ethics: The Education of Desire.” International

Studies in Philosophy 22 (3): 59–78. doi:10.5840/intstudphil19902235.

Rosenthal, M. A. 2002. “Why Spinoza Chose the Hebrews: The Exemplary Function of Prophecy in the Theological-Political Treatise.” In Jewish Themes in Spinoza’s Philosophy, edited by L. Goodman and H. M. Ravven, 225–260. New York: SUNY Press.

Sanderse, W. 2013. “The Meaning of Role Modelling in Moral and Character Education.” Journal of Moral Education 42 (1): 28–42. doi:10.1080/03057240.2012.690727.

Steinberg, J.2014.“Following a Recta Ratio Vivendi: The Practical Utility of Spinoza’s Dictates of Reason.” In Essays on Spinoza’s Ethical Theory, edited by M. J. Kisner and A. Youpa, 178–196. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Steinberg, J. 2018a. “Two Puzzles Concerning Spinoza’s Conception of Belief.” European Journal of Philosophy 26 (1): 261–282. doi:10.1111/ejop.v26.1.

Steinberg, J.2018b. Spinoza’s Political Psychology: The Taming of Fortune and Fear. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Vansieleghem, N. 2005. “Philosophy for Children as the Wind of Thinking.” Journal of Philosophy of Education 39: 19–35. doi:10.1111/j.0309-8249.2005.t01-1-00417.x.

Zagzebski, L.2010.“Exemplarist Virtue Theory.” Metaphilosophy 41 (1–2): 41–57. doi:10.1111/ meta.2010.41.issue-1-2.

Zagzebski, L. 2013. “Moral Exemplars in Theory and Practice.” Theory and Research in Education 11 (2): 193–206. doi:10.1177/1477878513485177.

Zagzebski, L. 2015. “Admiration and the Admirable.” Aristotelian Society 89 (1): 205–221. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8349.2015.00250.x.

References

Related documents

46 Konkreta exempel skulle kunna vara främjandeinsatser för affärsänglar/affärsängelnätverk, skapa arenor där aktörer från utbuds- och efterfrågesidan kan mötas eller

För att uppskatta den totala effekten av reformerna måste dock hänsyn tas till såväl samt- liga priseffekter som sammansättningseffekter, till följd av ökad försäljningsandel

Från den teoretiska modellen vet vi att när det finns två budgivare på marknaden, och marknadsandelen för månadens vara ökar, så leder detta till lägre

The increasing availability of data and attention to services has increased the understanding of the contribution of services to innovation and productivity in

Generella styrmedel kan ha varit mindre verksamma än man har trott De generella styrmedlen, till skillnad från de specifika styrmedlen, har kommit att användas i större

I regleringsbrevet för 2014 uppdrog Regeringen åt Tillväxtanalys att ”föreslå mätmetoder och indikatorer som kan användas vid utvärdering av de samhällsekonomiska effekterna av

Parallellmarknader innebär dock inte en drivkraft för en grön omställning Ökad andel direktförsäljning räddar många lokala producenter och kan tyckas utgöra en drivkraft

Närmare 90 procent av de statliga medlen (intäkter och utgifter) för näringslivets klimatomställning går till generella styrmedel, det vill säga styrmedel som påverkar