• No results found

Ethics in school: a study of the foundation and methods for value communication

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2022

Share "Ethics in school: a study of the foundation and methods for value communication"

Copied!
6
0
0

Loading.... (view fulltext now)

Full text

(1)

Ethics
in
School


A
study
of
the
foundation
and
methods
for
value
communication.


Viktor
Gardelli1,
Anders
Persson,
Liza
Haglund,
&
Ylva
Backman


1.
Introduction


This
article
is
about
a
project
concerning
a
coherentist
approach
to
ethics
in
 school.
The
project
has
two
main
parts;
one
theoretical
and
one
empirical.
The
 former
focuses
on
philosophical
problems
and
issues
concerning
coherentism
as
 a
metaethical
position
in
general,
and
particularly
when
applied
to
the
field
of
 value
education,
and
the
latter
aims
to
study
some
consequences
of
a
coherentist
 approach
to
the
study
of
discussing
ethical
matters
with
children.


2.
Coherentism


Coherentism
is
an
epistemological
theory
in
the
philosophical
field
of
inquiry
 concerning
justification
of
beliefs,
propositions
and
statements.
The
main
 alternative
to
coherentism
is
called
foundationalism,
and
it
has
been
the


historically
dominant
position.
What
is
justification,
and
what
is
its
relevance?
A
 justification
of
a
certain
belief
is
some
reason
to
uphold
the
belief,
i.e.
it
is
a
good
 reason
to
believe
the
thing
in
question.
For
example,
we
might
believe,
similarly
 to
a
physics
professor,
that
the
sun
is
a
sphere
of
gas.
There
are
some
differences
 in
the
two
cases,
though,
being
that
the
physics
professor
is
more
justified
in
his
 belief
than
we
are.
She
can
probably
give
a
lot
of
arguments
for
believing
that
the
 sun
consists
of
gas.
These
arguments
are
taken
to
justify
her
belief.



According
to
foundationalism,
there
are
two
radically
different
kinds
of
 







1
Corresponding
author:
Viktor
Gardelli,
Luleå
University
of
Technology
 (www.ltu.se).
Email:
viktor.gardelli@ltu.se.



(2)

beliefs:
foundational
ones
and
non‐foundational
ones
(Fumerton,
2002;
Goldman


&
Pust,
1998;
Levin,
2005).
The
non‐foundational
ones
are
justified
in
case
they
 are
justified
by
foundational
beliefs
(or
by
other
non‐foundational
beliefs
which
 are
in
turn
justified
by
foundational
beliefs,
i.e.
transitively
justified,
in
the
end
by
 foundational
beliefs).
There
are
different
positions
regarding
the
foundational
 beliefs,
which
lead
to
different
kinds
of
foundationalism
(Fumerton,
2002).
These
 theories
have
theoretical
problems
that
needs
to
be
solved.
Common
to
all
of
 them
is
the
idea
that
some
beliefs,
the
foundational
ones,
necessarily
stand
in
a
 justification‐relation
to
other
beliefs
(non‐foundational
ones)
in
only
one
 direction.
We
can,
somewhat
metaphorically,
imagine
the
belief
system
as
a
 tower,
where
the
base
supports
the
top,
but
not
the
opposite.
Justification
goes
 bottom‐up
(at
least
regarding
the
foundational
layer).



Coherentists,
in
opposition
to
foundationalists,
deny
the
distinction
between
 foundational
and
non‐foundational
beliefs
(Fumerton,
2002).
A
coherentist
 claims
that
every
belief
in
a
belief
system
needs
justification,
and
indeed
can
get
 justification,
from
other
beliefs
in
the
system
(Goodman,
1965).
One
might
speak
 of
such
a
coherentistic
system
of
beliefs
as
a
web
of
belief,
where
there
might
be
 more
or
less
central
beliefs,
but
where
the
justification
relation
(possibly)
holds
 both
ways
between
any
two
statements.



According
to
at
least
some
coherentists,
a
system
of
beliefs
can
cohere
in
 different
degrees,
and
a
certain
belief
can
cohere
in
different
degrees
to
a
certain
 set
of
other
beliefs.
A
specific
belief
is
more
justified
(to
a
person)
the
more
it
 coheres
with
his
or
hers
system
of
beliefs
(maybe
given
that
the
system
has
 reached
some
certain
standard,
or
such
that
it
is
more
justified
given
the
same
 amount
of
coherence,
the
higher
status,
due
to
e.
g.
being
bigger
and
more


coherent,
the
system
has).
We
strive,
one
could
say,
towards
a
state
where
every
 statement
coheres
to
a
high
degree
with
the
system.
This
is
called
a
reflective
 equilibrium
(Daniels,
1979;
Goodman,
1965;
Rawls,
1971;
Tersman,
1993).
It
is
 therefore
of
great
importance
that
we
can
specify
this
coherence‐relation.
Many
 have
attempted
to
do
this,
but
there
are
controversies
regarding
which
account
 is
correct.



(3)

Metaethical
coherentism
is
a
position
in
the
discussion
about
justification
of
 moral
judgements.
Metaethics
can
be
said
to
be
the
study
of
second‐order
ethical
 questions,
i.e.
questions
about
and
regarding
(first‐order)
ethical
questions,
 known
as
normative
ethical
questions,
such
as
“Is
it
morally
acceptable
to
kill
 and
eat
animals?”,
“Ought
one
to
give
to
the
poor?”,
“Is
war
morally
wrong?”,


“What
is
global
justice?”,
“What
is
the
value
of
liberty?”
and
so
on
(Miller,
2003;


Singer,
1994;
Tännsjö,
2000).
The
metaethical
questions
are
such
questions
as


“What
does
‘morally
wrong’
mean?”
“Is
there
such
a
thing
as
moral
facts?”,
“What
 is
value?”
and
“Can
we
have
moral
knowledge,
and
if
so,
what
is
justification
in
 ethics?”,
which
arises
about
the
field
of
normative
ethics
(Bergström,
2004;


Miller,
2003).
Metaethical
coherentism
is
concerned
with
the
last
half
of
the
last
 of
these
questions.
Analogously
with
ordinary
epistemological
coherentism,
 metaethical
coherentism
holds
that
moral
judgements
are
justified
if
they
cohere
 with
the
agent’s
web
of
judgements
(Bergström,
2004).


3.
Ethical
conflicts
in
School


In
Sweden,
one
of
the
main
purposes
of
the
educational
system
is
to
mediate
a


‘value
foundation’
(or
value
fundament)
based
on
Christian
ethical
tradition
and
 western
humanism
to
the
pupils
(Lpo94).
Suppose
now
that
you
have
a


foundationalist
approach
to
ethical
discussion
in
schools,
as
many
seem
to
have
 had
historically
(and
which
seems
to
correspond
well
with
the
idea
of
a
value
 foundation
or
fundament).
Suppose
furthermore
that
some
pupil
expresses
the
 judgement
that
some
of
his
classmates
have
a
lower
value
than
him,
due
to
e.g.


the
classmate
being
a
girl.
Hence,
it
seems
the
boy
does
not
believe
in
equality
in
 value
concerning
gender.
This
seemingly
anti‐egalitarian
judgement
conflicts
 with
the
judgement
that
gender
does
not
have
any
bearing
on
ones
value,
which
 is
included
in
the
value
foundation
of
the
educational
system.
The
teacher
is
 supposed
to
mediate
to
this
pupil
the
values
supported
by
the
educational
 system.
But
how
is
this
done?
What
are
the
features
of
this
situation?
According


(4)

to
a
foundationalist,
we
here
have
a
conflict
between
foundational
values,
or
so
 we
can
suppose.
In
this
case,
there
is
nothing
obvious
to
do
to
resolve
this
 conflict,
because
the
foundational
values
cannot
be
justified;
it
is
supposed
that
 we
simply
realise
the
correctness
of
them
by
our
moral
intuition,
or
something
 like
this.
Therefore,
there
is
a
conflict
between
what
the
teacher
ought
to
do
and
 what
she
in
fact
can
do.2



A
coherentist,
in
contrast
to
the
foundationalist,
could
point
to
how
the
two
 different
judgements
in
our
hypothetic
example
gain
different
amount
of
 justification
from
other
judgements,
and
thereby
hopefully
find
consensus,
and
 hence
dissolve
the
conflict.
Hopefully,
by
dialogue,
the
pupil
can
realise
that
his
 idea
of
the
different
values
of
him
and
his
classmate
does
not
cohere
as
well
with
 his
value
system
as
does
the
idea
of
gender
equality
and
the
insignificance
of
sex
 in
regard
to
value,
or,
if
this
is
not
the
case,
that
the
value
system
of
his
teacher
is
 more
coherent
than
his.



The
ability
to
(at
least
theoretically)
resolve
ethical
disputes
and
conflicts
 seems
to
speak
in
favour
of
coherentism.
As
noted
above,
coherentism
is
not
 theoretically
unproblematic,
though.
One
problem
is
how
to
understand
the
 justification‐relation.
What
does
it
mean
that
two
propositions
justify
each
 other?
What
is
coherence?
Philosophers
have
discussed
several
different


proposals
(Fumerton,
2002).
One
of
the
aims
of
the
further
work
in
this
project
is
 to
propose
and
evaluate
such
a
definition
of
coherence.



With
regard
to
methods
for
ethical
discussion
in
relation
to
a
coherentistic
 approach,
it
seems
as
a
“philosophy
with
children”
(Børresen
&
Malmhester,
 2004;
Haglund
&
Persson,
2004;
Juuso,
2007;
Lipman,
2003;
Malmhester
&


Ohlsson,
1999)
approach
will
seem
reasonable
and
fitting.




 










2
And
according
to
the
Kantian
principle
that
ought
implies
can,
it
seems
as
if
this
shows
that
if
you
 are
a
foundationalist,
you
must
conclude
that
it
cannot
be
the
goal
for
the
teacher
to
mediate
these
 values,
hence
the
foundationalist
seems
forced
to
believe
that
the
idea
behind
the
value
foundation
is
 misguided.
This
speaks
in
disfavour
of
foundationalism.


(5)


 
 


4.
References


Bergström,
L.
(2004).
Grundbok
i
värdeteori.
Stockholm:
Thales.


Børresen,
B.,
&
Malmhester,
B.
(2004).
Låt
barnen
filosofera
:
det
filosofiska
samtalet
 i
skolan.
Stockholm:
Liber.


Daniels,
N.
(1979).
Wide
Reflective
Equilibrium
and
Theory
Acceptance
in
Ethics.


The
Journal
of
Philosophy,
76(5),
256‐282.


Fumerton,
R.
(2002).
Theories
of
Justification.
In
P.
K.
Moser
(Ed.),
The
Oxford
 Handbook
of
Epistemology
(pp.
204‐233).
Oxford:
Oxford
University
Press.


Goldman,
A.,
&
Pust,
J.
(1998).
Philosophical
Theory
and
Intuitional
Evidence.
In
M.


R.
DePaul
(Ed.),
Rethinking
intuition
:
the
psychology
of
intuition
and
its
role
in
 philosophical
inquiry.
Lanham,
Md.:
Rowman
&
Littlefield.


Goodman,
N.
(1965).
Fact,
fiction
and
forecast
(2
ed.).
Indianapolis.


Haglund,
L.,
&
Persson,
A.
(2004).
Öppet
sinne,
stor
respekt.
Stockholm:
Rädda
 barnen.


Juuso,
H.
(2007).
Child,
Philosophy
and
Education.
Oulu:
Oulun
yliopisto.


Levin,
J.
(2005).
The
evidential
status
of
philosophical
intuition.
Philosophical
 Studies,
121(3),
193‐224.


Lipman,
M.
(2003).
Thinking
in
education.
Cambridge:
Cambridge
University
Press.


Malmhester,
B.,
&
Ohlsson,
R.
(1999).
Filosofi
med
barn
:
reflektioner
över
ett
försök
 på
lågstadiet.
Stockholm:
Carlsson.


Miller,
A.
(2003).
An
introduction
to
contemporary
metaethics.
Cambridge:
Polity.


Moser,
P.
K.
ed.
(2002).
The
Oxford
Handbook
of
Epistemology.
Oxford:
Oxford
 University
Press.


Rawls,
J.
(1971).
A
theory
of
justice.
Cambridge,
Mass.:
Harvard
University
Press.


Singer,
P.
ed.
(1994).
Ethics.
Oxford:
Oxford
University
Press.


(6)

Tersman,
F.
(1993).
Reflective
equilibrium
:
an
essay
in
moral
epistemology.


Stockholm:
Almqvist
&
Wiksell
International.


Tännsjö,
T.
(2000).
Grundbok
i
normativ
etik.
Stockholm:
Thales.


References

Related documents

The first aim is to say something about general philosophical questions relating to coherentism as a theory in metaethics, and especially in relation to value education; the

Industrial Emissions Directive, supplemented by horizontal legislation (e.g., Framework Directives on Waste and Water, Emissions Trading System, etc) and guidance on operating

One is questioning to what extent consumers find it important how suppliers (SCA as a seller) perceive the expectation of their customers. Also, to what extent does a supplier want

46 Konkreta exempel skulle kunna vara främjandeinsatser för affärsänglar/affärsängelnätverk, skapa arenor där aktörer från utbuds- och efterfrågesidan kan mötas eller

Both Brazil and Sweden have made bilateral cooperation in areas of technology and innovation a top priority. It has been formalized in a series of agreements and made explicit

The increasing availability of data and attention to services has increased the understanding of the contribution of services to innovation and productivity in

Generella styrmedel kan ha varit mindre verksamma än man har trott De generella styrmedlen, till skillnad från de specifika styrmedlen, har kommit att användas i större

I regleringsbrevet för 2014 uppdrog Regeringen åt Tillväxtanalys att ”föreslå mätmetoder och indikatorer som kan användas vid utvärdering av de samhällsekonomiska effekterna av