• No results found

Studies in the Conceptual Development of Mathematical Analysis

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "Studies in the Conceptual Development of Mathematical Analysis"

Copied!
32
0
0

Loading.... (view fulltext now)

Full text

(1)UPPSALA DISSERTATIONS IN MATHEMATICS 64. Studies in the conceptual development of mathematical analysis Kajsa Bråting. Department of Mathematics Uppsala University UPPSALA 2009.

(2) . 

(3)         

(4)          

(5)

(6)   !  "  # $%&&' !&(!$)

(7)   

(8) ) 

(9) 

(10) 

(11) )* 

(12) 

(13)  +,   

(14) -

(15)   .  +   / 0  1+%&&'+2   3

(16)   

(17)  

(18) )4   5 + 4  6 7    

(19)  +  

(20)   

(21)  89+:!+  + ,6%1';<'!$&8%&<&!+ , . 

(22)  -  

(23)  

(24) )   

(25)  )

(26)   

(27)          + 7      

(28)  

(29) ) 

(30)             !'   

(31)  +,  

(32)  

(33) )      +7   )    -    2-    .+=+/>  ?

(34)  

(35) 

(36)  )

(37)  

(38)    

(39)  

(40) - 3  ? 

(41) )

(42) !<%!+7 

(43)  

(44) 

(45) />  ? 

(46)    

(47)  -  

(48)  

(49)      . 

(50) 

(51) ) 3  ?  

(52)  @!A + B 

(53)  

(54)   />  ? 

(55)    

(56)  

(57)    -

(58) ) = . =     

(59)  -  

(60)     + 7   

(61)     -    C 

(62)       )

(63)  

(64)          + B 

(65)   

(66)  

(67)       . 

(68) 

(69) )   

(70)      6      + B 

(71)  

(72)    

(73) 

(74) ) -   C 

(75)            

(76) +7      -     -      

(77) 

(78)          

(79)    

(80) )  C 

(81) +7      -

(82)  3  ? 

(83) 

(84) 

(85) -   

(86) 

(87) ) 

(88)  )  

(89) 

(90)   

(91) )   - .  .+=+/>   !<$%+B />  ?  ? 3  ?))  

(92)  

(93) )

(94)    

(95)  )  

(96)   

(97) -  +7      - 

(98)  

(99) 

(100) )   

(101) ))    

(102)       !'   +B  3  ?   ?

(103)

(104) )

(105) )3  ? 

(106) 

(107) 

(108) -   

(109) 

(110) )

(111)  )  

(112)  

(113)  

(114)    

(115) )  

(116) - )  

(117) 

(118) ) )   

(119)   

(120) + 

(121)  

(122) 

(123) )  

(124)   

(125)         

(126)  

(127) 

(128)   !"#  $

(129)  %&'()#*  %

(130) 

(131)  D1 > / 0  %&&' 722E!9&!%&9' 72/E';<'!$&8%&<&!  (  ((( !&!:9'F. (AA +6+A 

(132) G @ (  ((( !&!:9'H.

(133) List of Papers. This thesis is based on the following papers, which are referred to in the text by their Roman numerals. I Bråting, K. (2007). A new look at E.G. Björling and the Cauchy sum theorem. Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 61(5): 519535. II Bråting, K., Pejlare, J. (2008). Visualizations in mathematics. Erkenntnis, 68(3): 345-358. III Bråting, K. (2009). E.G. Björling’s view of power series expansions of complex valued functions. Manuscript. Reprints were made with permission from the publishers..

(134)

(135) Contents. 1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1.1 Analysis during the 19th century . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1.2 Visualizations and formal definitions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2 Summary of the papers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2.1 Paper I . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2.2 Paper II . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2.3 Paper III . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3 Summary in Swedish . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 4 Acknowledgements . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Bibliography . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. 7 7 11 17 17 19 20 23 27 29.

(136)

(137) 1. Introduction. In this thesis I consider the development of certain mathematical concepts from a historical and didactical point of view. In particular, I have studied the conceptual development in analysis during the mid-19th century, for instance, concepts such as functions, continuity, convergence and infinite series have been investigated. I have studied the use of basic concepts in connection with two important theorems: Cauchy’s sum theorem from 1821 and Cauchy’s theorem on power series expansions of complex valued functions from 1840. In the thesis I also consider the role of visualizations in mathematics from a historical and didactical perspective. The visualizations have been considered on the basis of historical examples as well as on my own empirical studies.. 1.1 Analysis during the 19th century In the history of mathematics the 19th century is often considered as a period when mathematical analysis underwent a major change. There was an increasing concern for the lack of rigor in analysis concerning basic concepts, such as functions, derivatives, and real numbers.1 Mathematics was often connected to the intuition of time and space.2 The definitions of many fundamental concepts in analysis were vague and gave rise to different views of not only the definitions, but also of the theorems involving these concepts. Furthermore, mathematicians did not always use the same definition of the fundamental concepts. For instance, the Belgian mathematician A.H.E. Lamarle (1806–1875) had a different way of defining certain complex valued functions compared to the French mathematician A.L. Cauchy (1789–1857). In paper III in this thesis I suggest that this was the reason why Lamarle and Cauchy had different views regarding the appropriate sufficient condition for developing a complex valued function in a power series.. 1. Katz (1998, pp. 704–705). Jahnke (1993, p. 268) discusses a new emerging attitude among mathematicians during the mid-19th century whose aim was to erase the link between mathematics and the intuition of time and space. This will be discussed in the thesis at page 13.. 2. 7.

(138) Another problem during the mid-19th century was that some definitions allowed surprising examples. For instance, in 1821 Cauchy claimed that the sum function of a convergent series of real-valued continuous functions was continuous. However, a couple of years later Abel (1802– 1829) came up with exceptions to the theorem and later also corrections of the theorem were suggested (see below). Abel constructed a completely new type of functions3 that Cauchy probably had not anticipated when he formulated his theorem in 1821. However, it was not only the new functions that led to problems regarding the validity of Cauchy’s sum theorem. It seems that the mathematical theory had reached a point where the convergence condition was not precise enough to exclude counterexamples such as Abel’s. It turned out that a series of functions can converge in different ways and that it was necessary to specify the convergence condition in Cauchy’s theorem. In fact, there were already attempts to distinguish between different convergence concepts. For instance, in 1846 the Swedish mathematician E.G. Björling (1808–1872) tried to explain and prove Cauchy’s sum theorem on the basis of his own distinction between ‘convergence for every value of x’ and ‘convergence for every given value of x’, where the former notion was the stronger condition of convergence. Perhaps ‘convergence for every value of x’ in connection with Cauchy’s sum theorem was an attempt to express what in modern terminology could be described as  n  ∞      sup  fk (x) − fk (x) → 0   x k=1. (1.1). k=1. when n → ∞, that is uniform convergence of the partial sums. However, one problem for Björling was that he did not have a proper way of connecting the two variables n and x. As Grattan-Guinness4 points out, during the 19th century there was a problem to distinguish between the expressions ‘for all x there is a y such that...’ and ‘there is a y such that for all x...’. Stokes (1847) and Seidel (1848) suggested corrections of Cauchy’s sum theorem and in 1853 Cauchy modified his own theorem by adding a stronger convergence conditition to his 1821 version.5 The convergence concept was probably not the only reason for the controversies regarding Cauchy’s sum theorem. One should also have in mind that in the mid-19th century a function was often simply an 3. The invention of functions that were sums of trigonometric series, for instance sin x + 12 sin 2x − 13 sin 3x + · · · (see Abel, 1826, p. 16). 4 Grattan-Guinness (2000, p. 70). 5 Cauchy (1853, p. 33) added that the series of real valued continuous functions had to be always convergent, which sometimes has been interpreted as the modern notion of uniform convergence.. 8.

(139) expression containing the variable x.6 A function did not need to be single-valued, for instance, Björling considered the function x f (x) = (1.2) |x| as two-valued at x = 0. One problem of allowing functions to attain many values is that it becomes difficult to conclude what limit function a certain sequence of functions converges to. Without a proper definition it can be difficult to decide what value the function √ √ x− a f (x) = (1.3) x−a attains at x = a. In modern mathematics this is not a problem since function (1.3) is not defined at x = a. That is, unlike early 19th century mathematics, we do not define functions today without specifying their domains. Björling7 on the other hand, considered f (a) as a removable discontinuity when he stated that the function (1.3) attains the value 1 √ at x = a, since 2 a 1 lim f (a + Δ) = √ . (1.4) Δ→0 2 a Björling applied a certain rule which said that at x = x0 the value of the function could be obtained in two different ways; either it was obtained ‘immediately’ by putting x = x0 into the expression containing a variable, or the value of the function could be obtained as the limit when x tends to x0 . Since functions were considered as variable expressions it was not surprising that mathematicians had to construct certain rules as supplements to the function definitions. When the variable expressions became complicated enough the mathematicians ‘empirically’ discovered new properties of the functions, that is they read off properties from the expression that was written up. To be speculative, perhaps the vague definitions during the first half of the 19th century led to the fact that mathematicians had to come up with certain rules in order to obtain a coherent theory. One problem may have been that these rules were not generally accepted and therefore could cause a great deal of confusion. The development of analysis in the mid-19th century has been described several times in the history of mathematics. For instance, Laugwitz8 considers the 19th century as a ‘turning point’ in the ontology as well as the method of mathematics. He argues that instead of using 6. Björling (1852, p. 171). Ibid., p. 174. 8 Laugwitz (1999, p. 301). 7. 9.

(140) mathematics as a tool for computations, the emphasis fell on conceptual thinking. Laugwitz continues: The supreme mastery of computational transformations by Gauss, Jacobi, and Kummer was beyond doubt but had reached its practical limits (Laugwitz, 1999, p. 303).. There are several examples indicating that mathematics during the first half of the 19th century still was considered more as ‘a tool for computations’ rather than a study of abstract objects. One example is J.L. Lagrange’s (1736–1813) way of considering functions. He stated: One calls a function of one or several quantities any expression for calculation in which these quantities enter in any manner whatever, mingled or not with some other quantities which are regarded as being given and invariable values, the quantities of the function can take all possible values (Lagrange, 1847, p. 1).. Sørensen (2005) makes a similar distinction as Laugwitz when he stresses that from the mid-18th century to the mid-19th century research in analysis underwent a change from being formula-centered to being concept-centered. According to Sørensen, mathematicians in the mid-18th century dealt with arguments based on manipulations of formulas; their questions concerned formulas and the results obtained were formulas. Meanwhile, in the mid-19th century [...] new types of questions arose and were answered by analyses of the extensions of concepts and of relations between concepts (Sørensen, 2005, p. 477).. Sørensen makes a comparison between Abel’s mathematical approach and Cauchy’s approach to mathematics. According to Sørensen, the former had a formula-centered approach and the latter a concept-centered approach. Among other things this is a conclusion based on their different reactions to Cauchy’s sum theorem (that is, the same theorem which was discussed above). Sørensen argues that Abel was more concerned about limiting the number of functions which were exceptions to the theorem by requiring a special form for these functions. Meanwhile, Cauchy was focusing on his concept of convergence from 1821 and [...] he [Cauchy] made extra requirements concerning the nature of convergence (Sørensen, 2005, p. 471).. Sørensen’s point is that in 1853 Cauchy was more concerned about the nature of the convergence concept and therefore had a more conceptcentered approach to mathematics compared to Abel. However, Cauchy was probably influenced by the development during these 30 years.. 10.

(141) Jahnke9 describes the 19th century as a period when mathematicians and natural scientists changed their attitude towards the relationship between science and practice, at least in Germany. He argues that in the natural sciences the ambition of requiring new empirical knowledge became less important, instead, science should focus on the ‘understanding of nature and culture’.10 Jahnke claims that the emerging new attitude in the sciences led to a sometimes ‘anti-Kantian’ view of mathematics that sought to break the link between mathematics and the intuition of time and space.11 Jahnke writes: Rather than considering pure mathematics in terms of algorithmic procedures for calculating certain magnitudes, the emphasis fell on understanding certain relations from their own presuppositions in a purely conceptual way. To understand given relations in and of themselves one must generalize them and see them abstractly (Jahnke, 1993, p. 267).. The descriptions by Laugwitz, Sørensen and Jahnke of the development of analysis during the 19th century are quite similar and this will be summarized in Figure 1.1 below.. 1.2 Visualizations and formal definitions The status of visualizations has varied from time to time. Mancosu12 points out that during the 19th century visual thinking fell into disrepute. The reason may have been that mathematical claims that seemed obvious on account of an intuitive and immediate visualization, turned out to be incorrect with the new emerging mathematical methods and results. He exemplifies this with K. Weierstrass’ (1815–1897) construction of a continuous but nowhere differentiable function from 1872.13 An early example of a discussion on the role of intuition and visual thinking in mathematics is the 17th century debate between the philosopher Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679) and the mathematician John Wallis 9. Jahnke (1993, p. 266). Ibid., p. 267. 11 Jahnke (1993, p. 268) is quoting Fries (1822) who argued that “the notion became more and more common that the objects of mathematics are purely mental constructions produced by man’s faculty of productive imagination”. 12 Mancosu (2005, p. 13). 13 In 1872 Weierstrass constructed the function 10. f (x) =. . bn cos (an x)π,. where x is a real number, a is odd, 0 < b < 1 and ab > 1 + 3π/2, which was published by du Bois Reymond (1875, p. 29).. 11.

(142) Mathematical analysis. 1700. 1800. Empirical. Intuitive. Formulacentered. 1900. Conceptual. Abstract. Conceptcentered. Figure 1.1: An overview of the development of mathematical analysis on the basis of Laugwitz (1999), Jahnke (1993) and Sørensen (2005).. (1616–1703). One of their disputes concerned the relationship between the finite and the infinite, which have been discussed by among others Mancosu (1996) and Bråting & Öberg (2005). Mancosu points out that the usage of new methods based on calculations with indivisibles led to that the concept of volume underwent a considerable change.14 Solids of infinite lenghts but with finite volumes were introduced. For instance, if one revolves the function y = x1 around the x-axis and cuts the obtained solid with a plane perpendicular to the x-axis, one obtains a solid of infinite length but with finite volume. Sometimes this solid is referred to as ‘Torricelli’s infinitely long solid’ (see Figure 3 in Paper II in this thesis). Hobbes rejected the existence of such solids. He insisted that every object must exist in the universe and be perceived by the ‘natural light’.15 Hobbes stressed that when mathematicians spoke of, for instance, an ‘infinitely long line’ this would be interpreted as a line which could be extended as much as one prefered to. He argued that infinite objects had no material base and therefore could not be perceived by 14. Mancosu (1996, p. 39) refers to the Italian mathematician E. Cavalieri’s (1598–1647) geometry of indivisibles from the 1630s. 15 Mancosu (1996, pp. 137–138) states that many 17th century philosophers held that geometry provides us with indisputable knowledge and that all knowledge involves a set of self-evident truths known by ‘natural light’.. 12.

(143) the ‘natural light’.16 According to Hobbes, it was not possible to speak of an ‘infinitely long line’ as something given. The same thing was valid for solids of infinite lenght but with finite volume. It seems that Wallis, however, shared Leibniz’ opinion that it was nothing more spectacular about ‘Torricelli’s infinitely long solid’ than for instance that the infinite series 1 1 1 1 1 + + + + + · · · = 1.17 2 4 8 16 32 If the new method led to the result that infinite solids could have finite volumes, then these solids existed within a mathematical context. Meanwhile, it seems that the problem for Hobbes was that he made no strong distinction between mathematical objects and other objects. The 19th century mathematician Björling had a tendency to sometimes consider mathematical definitions as descriptions of entities rather than conventions. For instance, Björling defined a function as [...] an analytical expression which contains a real variable x (Björling, 1852, p. 171).. Björling certainly defined functions but sometimes he seems to consider the definition as describing something that already exists. As a consequence of his definition of a function, Björling considered every expression containing a variable that could be written up as a function. Let us consider three functions that Björling was discussing in a paper from 1852 (where the first two functions were considered in Section 1.1 above). In modern terminology these three functions would be expressed as; √ √ x x− a f (x) = , g(x) = and h(x) = |x|. (1.5) |x| x−a These functions are graphically represented in Figure 1.2 below. Björling considered f (x) as two-valued at x = 0. However, it has no derivative at x = 0 since the function representing the derivative jumps at x = 0. The 1 function g(x) attains the one value 2√ at x = a, since a 1 lim g(a + Δ) = √ . 2 a. Δ→0. In modern terminology we would say that Björling considers g(a) as a removable discontinuity. Björling did not consider whether the derivative of g(x) at x = a existed or not, but probably (on the basis of similar examples in Björling, 1852) Björling would say that the derivative at 16 17. Ibid., p. 147. Ibid., p. 143.. 13.

(144) f(x). g(x). 1 0. h(x). 1 0 0 1. a 1 0. Figure 1.2: A graphical representation of how Björling may have considered the functions f , g and h.. x = a was equal to − 8a1√a since lim. Δ→0. g(a + Δ) − g(a) 1 =− √ . Δ 8a a. (1.6). The function h(x) attains 0 at x = 0 and the derivative at x = 0 exists and is equal to the two values ±1.18 On the basis of these three examples, it seems that Björling’s approach was to investigate the behaviour of mathematical objects on the account of their ‘natural properties’. At least one gets the impression that, for Björling, it was already presupposed that the expression written on the paper was a function and the task for Björling was to discover their exact properties. For instance, it seems that Björling tried to find answers in the graphs of the functions. A closely related issue in the theory of visualizations comes up in Giaquinto’s claim19 that visual thinking can be a means of discovery in geometry but only in severely restricted cases in analysis. He suggests that visualizing becomes unreliable whenever it is used to discover the existence or nature of the limit of some infinite processes. One gets the impression that Giaquinto tries to distinguish between a ‘visible mathematics’ and a ‘less visible mathematics’. However, to divide mathematics in such a way can be interpreted as if one part of mathematics is more directly connected to empirical reality and the other part is abstract.20 18. Björling (1852, p. 177) claimed that generally, the derivative of a function f (x), at a specific point x0 , could only obtain ‘a finite and determined quantity’ if f (x0 ) was single-valued. 19 Giaquinto (1994, p. 789). 20 Giaquinto (1994, p. 804) claims that geometric concepts are idealizations of concepts with physical instances, meanwhile, the basic concepts of analysis are non-visual since they are not equivalent to any (known) concepts which can be conveyed visually.. 14.

(145) It seems that Giaquinto does not take into account what he wants to visualize and to whom. That is, the meaning of a visualization may be different depending on the observer. A concrete example is when a teacher illustrates a circle by drawing it on the blackboard, as in Figure 1.3 below. The picture on the blackboard is not a circle, since it is impossible to draw a perfect circle. But for a person who knows that a circle is a set of points in the plane that are equidistant from the midpoint, the picture on the blackboard is sufficient to understand that the teacher is talking about a ‘mathematical’ circle. However, for a child who has never heard of a circle before, the figure of the blackboard probably means something else. By looking at the circle in Figure 1.3 the child. Figure 1.3: ‘The circle on the blackboard’.. may even think that a circle is a ring which is not connected at the top. The point is that a visualization may not reveal its intended meaning to the observer. Instead, the visualization ‘leaves much unsaid’, for instance when we are drawing a line it is a ‘lenght without breadth’. However, with enough mathematical experience we can spell out what is unsaid ‘between the lines’,21 we can ‘see’ that the line is without width.22 Hence, visual images can certainly be sufficient for convincing oneself of the truth of a statement in mathematics, provided that one has sufficient knowledge of what they represent. In this thesis, one way to interpret Björling’s work has been to distinguish between mathematical objects as ‘natural’ and mathematical objects as ‘conventional’. It should be pointed out that the purpose has not been to classify Björling’s mathematics as one or the other, but it is noticable that Björling lived during a time period when mathematics underwent a considerable change. One can discern the ‘old’ mathematical approach as well as the ‘new’ mathematical approach in Björling’s work. For instance, Björling had an ‘old-fashioned’ way of considering functions when he sometimes considered them as something that already existed 21. Stenlund (2005, p. 46) uses this terminology in the context of spoken communication. A similar expression is used by Arcavi (2005, p. 216) when he argues that with enough mathematical knowledge we are able to ‘see the unseen’ in a visualization.. 22. 15.

(146) and the definition worked as a description. At the same time, Björling tried to develop new concepts in mathematics such as the distinction between ‘convergence for every given value of x’ and ‘convergence for every value of x’. This may of course be seen as we evaluate Björling’s mathematical efforts on the basis of today’s mathematical criteria. Grattan-Guinness23 considers two different approaches of interpreting the history of mathematics; the ‘history approach’ and the ‘heritage approach’. The former approach can typically be connected to details in the development of specific concepts or to chronology. Meanwhile, he refers ‘heritage’ to ...the impact of a notion upon later work, both at the time and afterward, especially the forms which it may take, or to be embodied, in later contexts (Grattan-Guinness, 2004, p. 165).. Grattan-Guinness points out that both the ‘history’ and the ‘heritage’ approaches are legitimate and important in their own right, but they are often mixed up.. 23. Grattan-Guinness (2004, pp. 164–165).. 16.

(147) 2. Summary of the papers. 2.1 Paper I Parts of this paper has been presented at the conference ‘History and Pedagogy of Mathematics’ in Uppsala, 2004. In this paper I study the Swedish mathematician E.G. Björling’s (1846, 1853) contribution to uniform convergence in connection to Cauchy’s theorem on the continuity of an infinite series. Cauchy1 claimed that a convergent series of real valued continuous functions is a continuous function. However, the proof was relatively imprecise which has led to different interpretations of the formulation of the theorem. The contemporary mathematicians criticized Cauchy’s sum theorem and came up with counterexamples. Historians of mathematics have argued about what Cauchy really meant by convergence and continuity, but also what he meant by a function. If one assumes that Cauchy meant pointwise convergence then the theorem is false. However, if he meant uniform convergence then the theorem is true. In 1853 Cauchy corrected his theorem by changing to the stronger convergence condition “always convergent”.2 But between the years 1821 and 1853 both exceptions (Abel, 1826) and corrections (Stokes, 1847, Seidel, 1848) to Cauchy’s 1821 theorem appeared. For instance, Abel3 showed that the trigonometric series 1 1 sin x + sin 2x + sin 3x + · · · (2.1) 2 3 was an exception to Cauchy’s sum theorem, since although (2.1) was a convergent series of real valued continuous functions, the sum was discontinuous at x = (2k + 1)π for each integer k (see Figure 2.1 below). A standard theorem in modern analysis is the following: If a sequence of real valued continuous functions, fn , converges uniformly to a function f , then f is a continuous function. In this case uniform convergence means that the maximum value of |fn (x) − f (x)| → 0 when n → 0. That is, for each n we choose the ‘worst’ x, which makes |fn (x) − f (x)| as large as possible. If this absolute value still ‘tends to 0’ while ‘n tends 1. Cauchy (1821, pp. 131–132). Grattan-Guinness (1986, pp. 231–232) argues that Cauchy (1853, p. 33) was influenced by Björling (1846, p. 66). 3 Abel (1826, p. 316). 2. 17.

(148) 2. . . 2. Figure 2.1: A graphical representation of the sum of the series sin x + 12 sin 2x + 1 3 sin 3x + · · ·. to infinity’ then fn converges uniformly to f . One obtains Cauchy’s sum  theorem for fn (x) = nk=1 gk (x), where gk are continuous functions. There are various interpretations of Cauchy’s sum theorem, for instance, the non-standard analysis interpreters Schmieden and Laugwitz4 claim that Cauchy’s sum theorem was correct, at least if one uses their own theory based on infinitesimals. In this paper this interpretation, among others, has been problematized. One of the questions has been how to interpret Cauchy’s use of expressions like for instance x = n1 . Giusti5 argues that x = n1 should be seen as an ordinary sequence having 0 as a limit, whereas, Laugwitz6 claims that the expression is an infinitesimal quantity generated by the sequence 1/n. If one uses the latter interpretation it appears that Cauchy’s 1821 theorem was correct. In fact, by using Laugwitz’ infinitesimal theory one can even show that Cauchy’s convergence condition from 1821 was weaker than uniform convergence, yet sufficient for the theorem to be true.7 In this paper I point out that such an interpretation presupposes a modern function concept, which was not available for Cauchy and Björling. For instance, Björling defined a function as “...an analytical expression which contains a variable x” 8 . I argue that with such an imprecise way of defining functions it seems unlikely that a weaker convergence concept than uniform convergence can guarantee continuity in the limit. We have considered Björling’s proof of the sum theorem by investigating his own distinction between ‘convergence for every value of x’ and ‘convergence for every given value of x’, where the former notion is a stronger criterion of convergence. In fact, ‘convergence for every value of x’ could have been an attempt to express uniform convergence. However, the problem for Björling was to connect the variables n and x, that is, ‘for each n there is an x such that...’. Another interpretation of ‘conver4. Schmieden and Laugwitz (1958, pp. 20–21). Giusti (1984, pp. 49–53). 6 Laugwitz (1980, p. 260). 7 Palmgren (2007, pp. 171–172). 8 Björling (1852, p. 171). 5. 18.

(149) gence for every value of x’ is that the x-values are not necessarily fixed. This could be seen as an attempt to compensate for Björling’s inability to connect the variables n and x.. 2.2 Paper II This paper is a joint work with Johanna Pejlare. The result has been presented at the conference ‘Towards a New Epistomology of Mathematics’ in Berlin, 2006. In the present paper visualizations in mathematics are considered from a historical and a didactical point of view. On the basis of some examples we study what a mathematical visualization can achieve. We argue that it is necessary to take into consideration the interaction between the visualization and the observer. In a historical study we consider Weierstrass’ construction of a continuous but nowhere differentiable function. Before this discovery, it was not an uncommon belief that a continuous function must be differentiable, except at isolated points.9 As a reaction to Weierstrass’ function, Klein10 tried to construct an abriged system of mathematics to avoid using results that he could not verify through ‘naive intuition’. It seems that Klein had a problem with visual thinking versus the formal development of mathematics in the wake of Weierstrass’ function. Furthermore, the Swedish mathematician Helge von Koch (1870–1924) was not satisfied with Weierstrass’ function since it was defined by an analytical expression whose geometrical nature was hidden.11 Therefore, von Koch constructed a continuous but nowhere differentiable function where it was possible to ‘see’ why the curve did not have a tangent. However, with support from our own study on university students, it appears that it is difficult for a person without sufficient mathematical knowledge to ‘see’ from a graphical representation that a function is continuous but nowhere differentiable. Visualizations leave much unsaid and depending on our experience with the mathematical theory we argue that we can ‘read’ what is unsaid ‘between the lines’. In another historical study we consider a debate from the 17th century between the philosopher Thomas Hobbes and the mathematician John Wallis regarding the ‘angle of contact’.12 The issue was whether there is an angle between a circle and its tangent, and if so what was the size of it? The ‘angle of contact’ is illustrated in Figure 2.2. 9. Mancosu (2005, p. 13). Klein (1873, p. 253). 11 von Koch (1906, pp. 145–146). 12 Prytz (2004, p. 11). 10. 19.

(150) ?. Figure 2.2: The ‘angle of contact’.. Wallis stressed that the ‘angle of contact’ was nothing, whereas, Hobbes argued that it was not possible that something which could be perceived from a picture could be nothing.13 However, one problem seems to be that they did not always base their arguments on mathematical definitions. Instead, they tried to ‘see’ the answer in the visualization. In the present paper we claim that a mathematical visualization can be interpreted in various ways depending on the context. For instance, the answer to the question whether the ‘angle of contact’ exists depends on which definition of an angle we use. Moreover, we point out that a mathematical visualization should be considered in a proper mathematical context. Furthermore, we discuss the role of mathematical visualizations in learning contexts. Giaquinto14 argues that visual thinking may be useful as illustration or to strengthen one’s grip on something independently known, in geometry and arithmetic, but it seems to fall short in elementary courses in analysis. We criticize Giaquinto’s theory since we believe that it is not correct to make a distinction between ‘visible’ and ‘less visible’ mathematics. One problem seems to be that Giaquinto does not take into account what we want to visualize and to whom. For a person who is not familiar with the relevant mathematical theory, a certain visualization may mean something completely different than for an educated mathematician. That is, we believe that mathematical visualizations do not have a sense independently of the observer.. 2.3 Paper III In this paper we consider Cauchy’s sufficient condition for developing a complex function of a complex variable in a power series. Cauchy claims that a complex function of a complex variable z can be expanded in a 13 14. Wallis (1685, p. 71) and Hobbes (1656, pp. 143–144). Giaquinto (2005, p. 789).. 20.

(151) power series if the function and its first derivative are continuous.15 However, the sufficiency regarding Cauchy’s continuity condition became controversial. On the basis of a paper written by the Swedish mathematician E.G. Björling I discuss a debate concerning this particular condition. For instance, Björling and the Belgian mathematician A.H.E. Lamarle (1806–1875) claimed that Cauchy’s condition from 1840 was insufficient. Björling argued that the function must have a continuous second derivative to guarantee that the function can be expanded in a power series.16 Meanwhile, Lamarle (1846, 1847) stressed that it was necessary to add a certain periodicity condition to Cauchy’s continuity condition. Cauchy and Björling criticized Lamarle when they claimed that the periodicity condition was superfluous since it followed from Cauchy’s continuity condition. In this paper we suggest that Lamarle’s periodicity condition is a consequence of the fact that Lamarle has another way to consider the complex numbers and another way of defining certain complex valued functions, compared to Cauchy and Björling. For instance, Lamarle defined the logarithm function of complex variables as l(reθi ) = l(r) + θi, where r is the absolute value and θ is the argument. Unlike Cauchy and Björling, he did not include any restriction for the argument θ within his definition. This means, in modern terminology, that Lamarle does not choose any branch for the argument, which probably is the reason why he had to add a periodicity condition to Cauchy’s continuity condition. In fact, on the basis of Lamarle’s definition of complex valued functions and his general view of complex numbers, the periodicity condition together with the continuity condition became, in his view, necessary and sufficient conditions for developing a complex valued function in a power series. Another reason why Cauchy’s theorem on power series expansions of complex functions was controversial could be the ambiguities of fundamental concepts in analysis that existed during the mid-19th century. The definitions of concepts such as functions, continuity and convergence were not generally accepted among mathematicians. In this paper we discuss this problem on the basis of a survey of fundamental concepts and propositions in analysis written by Björling in 1852. Cauchy, Lamarle and Björling had different proofs of the theorem on power series expansions of complex valued functions, which caused some confusion. Björling claimed that Lamarle’s proof was wrong and Cauchy’s proof was right. However, in this paper I argue that both Lamarle’s and 15 16. Cauchy (1840, p. 29). Björling (1852, p. 221).. 21.

(152) Cauchy’s proofs are correct on the basis of their own definitions of the fundamental concepts involved in the theorem.. 22.

(153) 3. Summary in Swedish. Den här avhandlingen behandlar utvecklingen av matematiska begrepp ur ett historiskt och didaktiskt perspektiv. Mera specifikt handlar det om begreppsutveckling inom den matematiska analysen under mitten av 1800-talet. De begrepp som studerats är bland annat funktioner, gränsvärden, konvergens och kontinuitet. Jag har studerat hur begreppen användes och vilken betydelse de hade i samband med vissa matematiska satser. De två satser som framförallt har behandlats är Cauchys summasats från 1821 och 1853, samt Cauchys sats angående potensserieutveckling av komplexvärda funktioner från 1840. Ett återkommande tema i avhandlingen har varit att studera vilken roll visualiseringar och ’intuitivt’ tänkande har inom matematiken, dels utifrån historiska exempel, dels utifrån mina egna empiriska undersökningar.. Analysens utveckling under 1800-talet I matematikhistorisk litteratur beskrivs 1800-talet som en period då den matematiska analysen genomgick en stor förändring. Vissa menar att det främsta syftet var att göra matematiken ’rigorös’, till exempel ville man inte längre att analysen skulle vara bunden till geometrin i samma utsträckning som tidigare. Funktioner, derivata och reella tal uppfattades ’intuitivt’, vilket man ville ändra på. Definitioner av fundamentala begrepp inom analysen var relativt oklara, vilket ibland gav upphov till olika tolkningar av vad begreppen egentligen betydde. Detta gjorde också att centrala satser inom analysen ibland blev ifrågasatta. Ett problem förefaller ha varit att definitionerna inte var allmänt vedertagna, det vill säga definitionen av ett specifikt matematiskt begrepp kunde skilja sig åt mellan olika matematiker. Tvister gällande giltigheten av vissa satser började uppkomma. Två orsaker till detta kan ha varit just oklara definitioner respektive bristen på allmänt vedertagna definitioner av fundamentala begrepp inom analysen. Ett exempel på en sats vars giltighet kom att ifrågasättas var Cauchys summasats från 1821. I satsen påstås det att en konvergent serie av reella kontinuerliga funktioner har en kontinuerlig summa. Beviset var relativt kortfattat och oprecist, vilket har lett till olika tolkningsförsök av vad. 23.

(154) Cauchy egentligen menade med satsen. Svårigheten har varit att förstå vad Cauchy menade med konvergens, men också vad han menade med kontinuitet och funktion. Man kan kanske tolka kontroverserna kring Cauchys summasats som en indikation på att det fanns ett behov av mer än ett konvergensbegrepp. Faktum är att det under mitten av 1800-talet redan fanns försök till att särskilja mellan olika konvergensbegrepp. Exempelvis försökte den svenske matematikern Björling som var flitig uttolkare av Cauchys matematik i största allmänhet, att förklara Cauchys summasats med hjälp av sin egen distinktion mellan ’konvergens för varje given x-valör’ respektive ’konvergens för alla x-valörer’.1 Ett sätt att tolka det senare starkare kriteriet är att den ’oberoende’ x-variabeln får variera med avseende på en annan aldrig specificerad variabel, för att kompensera för den allmängiltighet man vill uttrycka med likformig konvergens, det vill säga att   n ∞      sup  fk (x) − fk (x) → 0   x k=1. (3.1). k=1. då n → ∞. Distinktionen mellan ’konvergens för varje given x-valör’ respektive ’konvergens för alla x-valörer’ är oprecis på grund av att Björling inte hade något adekvat sätt att binda samman variablerna n och x, det vill säga ’för varje n existerar ett x så att...’. Ett annat begrepp som låg till grund för att giltigheten av Cauchys summasats blev ifrågasatt var funktionsbegreppet. Exempelvis G. Frege (1891) gjorde sig lustig över vissa 1800-talsmatematikers naiva funktionsbegrepp när han skrev att ’med en funktion av x förstås ett matematiskt uttryck som innehåller x, en formel som innefattar bokstaven x’. Uppenbarligen finns det svårigheter med att uttrycka olika typer av konvergens med ett så oprecist funktionsbegrepp. Den matematiska analysens utveckling under 1800-talet har beskrivits upprepade gånger inom den matematikhistoriska litteraturen. Exempelvis kallar Laugwitz2 1800-talet för en ’vändpunkt’ i samband med såväl den matematiska ontologin som dess metod. Laugwitz påstår att istället för att använda matematiken som ett beräkningsverktyg kom matematiken att baseras på begreppsorienterat tänkande. En liknande beskrivning gör Jahnke när han påstår att det under 1800-talet växte fram en ny attityd till vetenskap som innebar ett försök att bryta matematikens koppling till tid och rum.3. 1. Björling (1846, s. 21). Laugwitz (1999, s. 301). 3 Jahnke (1993, s. 268). 2. 24.

(155) Visualiseringar i matematiken Användningen av visualiseringar och intuitivt tänkande inom matematiken har ibland kritiserats. I ett historiskt perspektiv har visualiseringarnas status inom matematiken varierat under tidens lopp. Exempelvis påpekar Mancosu4 att i samband med Weierstrass konstruktion av en kontinuerlig men ingenstans deriverbar funktion sjönk visualiseringarnas status inom matematiken. På 1600-talet visade den italienske matematikern E. Torricelli (1608– 1647) att en oändligt utsträckt kropp kan ha en ändlig volym. Mancosu diskuterar bland annat Thomas Hobbes och John Wallis olika reaktioner på Torricellis exempel.5 Hobbes syn på oändligheten var baserad på hans empiristiska epistemologi. Han insisterade att alla objekt måste existera i universum och kunna uppfattas genom det ’naturliga ljuset’.6 Den svenske 1800-talsmatematikern Björling hade ibland en tendens att se matematiska definitioner som beskrivningar av vardagliga ting snarare än som konventioner. Björling uppfattade alla variabeluttryck som funktioner med ibland ’naturliga egenskaper’. Exempelvis ansåg Björling att funktionen x f (x) = |x| (uttryckt med moderna termer) antar de två värdena ±1 i x = 0. Men derivatan i samma punkt existerar inte eftersom funktionen som representerar derivatan hoppar i x = 0. Däremot existerar derivatan för funktionen g(x) = |x| i x = 0 och är lika med de två värdena ±1. Ett exempel från didaktiken som i viss mån liknar Björlings sätt att se på vissa matematiska objekt är när Giaquinto påstår att visualiseringar kan användas till att göra (personliga) upptäckter inom geometrin men oftast inte inom matematisk analys.7 Huvudskälet till detta är enligt Giaquinto att analysen innehåller beräkningar med gränsvärden baserade på oändliga processer. Ett sätt att tolka Giaquinto är att han gör en distinktion mellan ’visualiserbar matematik’ respektive ’mindre visualiserbar matematik’. En sådan indelning skulle kunna uppfattas som att en del av matematiken är knuten till en intuitivt tillgänglig verklighet medan en annan del är abstrakt. Vidare verkar det ibland som att Giaquinto inte tar hänsyn till vad vi vill visualisera och för vem. Det vill säga, innebörden av en visualisering kan enligt min mening vara olika beroende på vem det är som observerar. Ett konkret exempel är när man ritar en cirkel på ett papper (se Figur 1.3 i avsnitt 1.2 ovan). Figuren på papperet är, ur ett matematiskt per4. Mancosu (2005, s. 13). Mancosu (1996, s. 145–149). 6 Ibid., s. 137–138. 7 Giaquinto (1994, s. 789). 5. 25.

(156) spektiv, ingen cirkel eftersom det är omöjligt att rita en perfekt cirkel. För en person som redan vet att en cirkel är en mängd punkter med samma avstånd till mittpunkten ger figuren på papperet tillräckligt mycket information för att veta att vi talar om en ’matematisk’ cirkel. Men ett barn som aldrig kommit i kontakt med cirklar förut skulle kanske, genom att bara titta på figuren på papperet, kunna få uppfattningen att en cirkel är ungefär som en ring men som inte knyts ihop längst upp. I avhandlingen har ett sätt att tolka Björlings matematik varit att skilja mellan matematiska objekt som ’naturliga’ respektive konventionella. Syftet har inte varit att försöka klassificera Björlings matematik som exakt det ena eller det andra, utan istället att ha i åtanke att distinktionen mellan naturlig och konventionell matematik inte var självklar för Björling. Det märks relativt tydligt att Björling levde under en tid då matematiken genomgick en betydande förändring. Man kan skönja spår av såväl den ’gamla’ som ’nya’ matematiken i Björlings arbeten. Exempelvis hade Björling en ålderdomlig syn på funktioner samtidigt som han sysslade med att utveckla nya begrepp som till exempel distinktionen mellan ’konvergens för varje given x-valör’ och ’konvergens för alla x-valörer’.. 26.

(157) 4. Acknowledgements. There are several persons who have supported me during these years. Many thanks are due to... ...my advisor Anders Öberg. This thesis had not been carried out without your ideas and great skill in several research areas. Our discussions at Fågelsången have always been fruitful in many respects and I am looking forward to more of those discussions. ...my second advisor Gunnar Berg. I am very grateful for your valuable discussions, accurate translations and, of course, the nice conversations around the coffee table. ...all the other members of the HPM group; my co-author Johanna Pejlare for the enjoyable cooperation on visualizations in mathematics, Staffan Rodhe for your enthusiasm and expertice in the history of mathematics which have been helpful many times, but also a special thanks for supporting me in several other situations, Johan Prytz for valuable comments and suggestions, and Sten Kaijser for believing in me in the first place. ...The Bank of Sweden Tercentenary Foundations which has financially supported this thesis through The Research School of Mathematics Education. Thank you for the opportunity to pursue my research interest. ...all my friends at the department of Mathematics; Anna Petersson, Anders Pelander, Johanna Pejlare, Inga-Lena Assarsson, Sanja Babic, Björn Sandberg and many others for providing a friendly atmosphere. A special thanks to all members of Lilla μ for the enjoyable dinners. I am looking forward to more of them. ...my mum and dad for always being there for me. I really appreciate all your efforts to help me and my family in every situation. ...Britt and Terho for your warm hospitality. My trips to Borlänge have always been a great pleasure. ...Matthias for all your love and understanding. Two warm hugs to Vilmer and Alma for just being who you are.. 27.

(158)

(159) Bibliography. [1] N.H. Abel (1826), Untersuchungen über die Reihe, u.s.w., Journal für die reine und angewandte Mathematik, 1, 311–339. [2]. A. Arcavi (2003), The role of visual representations in the learning of mathematics, Educational studies in mathematics, 52, 215–241.. [3]. E.G. Björling (1846), Om en anmärkningsvärd klass af infinita serier, Kongl. Vetens. Akad. Förh. Stockholm, 13, 17–35.. [4]. E.G. Björling (1852), Om det Cauchyska kriteriet på de fall, då functioner af en variabel låta utveckla sig i serie, fortgående efter de stigande digniteterna af variabeln, Kongl. Vetens. Akad. Förh. Stockholm, 166–228.. [5] E.G. Björling (1853), Om oändliga serier, hvilkas termer äro continuerliga functioner af en reel variabel mellan ett par gränser, mellan hvilka serierna äro convergerande, Öfvers. Kongl. Vetens. Akad. Förh. Stockholm, 10, 147– 160. [6] K. Bråting and A. Öberg (2005), Om matematiska begrepp – en filosofisk undersökning med tillämpningar, Filosofisk Tidskrift, 26, 11–17. [7] A.L. Cauchy (1821), Cours d’analyse de l‘École royale polytechnique (Analyse Algébrique). [8] A.L. Cauchy (1840), Note sur l’intégration des équations différentielles des mouvements planétaires, Exerc. d’anal. et de phys. mathém. T. I. [9] A.L. Cauchy (1853), Note sur les séries convergentes dont les divers termes sont des fonctions continues d’une variable réelle ou imaginaire, entre des limites données, Oeuvres Complètes I, 12, 30–36. [10] P. du Bois-Reymond (1875), Versuch einer Classification der willkürlichen Functionen reeller Argumente nach ihren Aenderungen in den kleinsten Intervallen, Journal für die reine und angewandte Mathematik, 79, 21–37. [11] G. Frege (1891), Funktion och begrepp, i Gottlob Frege – Skrifter i urval, Thales 1995. [12] M. Giaquinto (1994), Epistemology of visual thinking in elementary real analysis, British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 45, 789–813. [13] E. Giusti (1984), Gli “errori” di Cauchy e i fondamenti dell’analisi, Bollettino di Storia delle Scienze Matematiche, 4, 24–54.. 29.

(160) [14] I. Grattan-Guinness (1986), The Cauchy–Stokes–Seidel story on uniform convergence: was there a fourth man?, Bull. Soc. Math. Belg., 38, 225–235. [15] I. Grattan-Guinness (2000), The search for mathematical roots 1870-1940, Princeton Paperbacks. [16] I. Grattan-Guinness (2004), The mathematics of the past: distinguishing its history from our heritage, Historia Mathematica, 31, 163–185. [17] T. Hobbes (1656), Six lessons to the professors of mathematics of the institution of Sir Henry Savile, London. [18] H.N. Jahnke (1993), Algebraic analysis in Germany, 1780–1840: Some mathematical and philosophical issues, Historia Mathematica, 20, 265–284. [19] V. Katz (1998), A history of mathematics: an introduction, AddisonWesley Educational Publishers, Inc. [20] F. Klein (1873), On the mathematical character of space-intuition and the relation of pure mathematics to the applied sciences, Evanston Colloquium, Lectures on Mathematics delivered at the North-western University Evanston from Aug. 28 to Sep. 9, 1893, also in F. Klein, Lectures on Mathematics, (2000), 41–50. [21] H. von Koch (1906), Une méthode géométrique élémentaire pour l’étude de certaines questions de la théorie des courbes planes, Acta Mathematica, 30, 145–174. [22] J.L. Lagrange (1847), Théorie des fonctions analytiques, second edition, Paris. [23] A.H.E. Lamarle (1846), Note sur le théorème de M. Cauchy rélatif au développ. des fonctions en séries, Liouville’s Journal T. XI, 129–141. [24] A.H.E. Lamarle (1847), Note sur la continuité considérée dans ses rapports avec la convergence des séries de Taylor et de Maclaurin, Liouville’s Journal T. XII, 305–342. [25] D. Laugwitz (1980), Infinitely small quantities in Cauchy’s textbooks, Historia Mathematica, 14, 258–274. [26] D. Laugwitz (1999), Bernhard Riemann – Turning points in the conceptions of mathematics, Birkhäuser Boston. [27] P. Mancosu (1996), Philosophy of mathematics and mathematical practise in the seventeenth century, Oxford University Press. [28] P. Mancosu (2005), Visualization in logic and mathematics. In P. Mancosu, K. F. Jörgensen, & S. A. Pedersen (Eds.) Visualization, explanation and reasoning styles in mathematics (pp. 13–28). Springer Verlag Dordrecht.. 30.

(161) [29] E. Palmgren (2007), Ickestandardanalys och historiska infinitesimaler, Normat, 55, 166–176. [30] J. Prytz (2004), A study of the angle of contact with a special focus on John Wallis’ conception on quantities and angles, Licentiate thesis, Uppsala University. [31] C. Schmieden and D. Laugwitz (1958), Eine Erweiterung der Infinitesimalrechnung, Mathematisches Zeitschrift, 69, 1–39. [32] P.L. Seidel (1848), Note über eine Eigenschaft der Reihen, welche Discontinuerliche Functionen darstellen, Abh. Akad. Wiss. München, 5, 381–393. [33] S. Stenlund (2005), Om “det outsagda”, Filosofisk tidskrift, 26, 45–54. [34] H.K. Sørensen (2005), Exceptions and counterexamples: Understanding Abel’s comment on Cauchy’s Theorem, Historia Mathematica, 32, 453–480. [35] G.G. Stokes (1847), On the critical values of the sums of periodic series. Trans. Cambridge Phil. Soc., 8 pp. 535–585. [36] J. Wallis (1685), A defense of the treatise of the angle of contact, appendix to Treatise of algebra, London.. 31.

(162)

(163)

References

Related documents

This study has gained knowledge about women in a higher leadership positions in Cambodia. To get a further understanding of women's leadership we suggest future research in this

But then, all the nodes (But node 1) updates their path to go to 0 for a longer one, but they cannot send a new update because in t=1 they already sent one and MRAI is not expired

Also, there is no need to make tests without a link failure detection mechanism or even with a Fast Ethernet link as the critical test link, since it is not likely that anything

This thesis will be about to survey the market for open source solutions providing Microsoft Exchange Protocol compliance that can be integrated to the back-end server API’s of

För att uppskatta den totala effekten av reformerna måste dock hänsyn tas till såväl samt- liga priseffekter som sammansättningseffekter, till följd av ökad försäljningsandel

Show that the uniform distribution is a stationary distribution for the associated Markov chain..

This paper expands the literature by investigating the convergence behaviour of carbon dioxide emissions in the Americas and the factors determining the formation

Moreover, we also establish two convergence results related to bounded function, which slightly extends the corresponding results in [2] in the sense that we consider a more