• No results found

Why Kant was completely right about space

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2022

Share "Why Kant was completely right about space"

Copied!
15
0
0

Loading.... (view fulltext now)

Full text

(1)

Why Kant was completely right about space

Why Kant was completely right about space

Helge Malmgren

Emeritus professor in theoretical philosophy

University of Gothenburg

Helge Malmgren

Emeritus professor in theoretical philosophy

University of Gothenburg NNPS 2017

Copenhagen

(2)

Plan for this lecture Plan for this lecture

 What did Kant say about space?

 Which are the standard objections to his view?

 Why all the standard objections are wrong

 Did Kant exclude other geometries than that of Euclid?

 The subjectivity of space

 Does Kant’s apriori conflict with empirical data?

 What did Kant say about space?

 Which are the standard objections to his view?

 Why all the standard objections are wrong

 Did Kant exclude other geometries than that of Euclid?

 The subjectivity of space

 Does Kant’s apriori conflict with empirical data?

 Why Euclidean space is a necessary condition for all empirical knowledge

 What is spatial intuition?

 What are the consequences of this necessity for the necessity of the synthetic apriori?

 Why Euclidean space is a necessary condition for all empirical knowledge

 What is spatial intuition?

 What are the consequences of this necessity for the necessity of the synthetic apriori?

(3)

What did Kant say about space?What did Kant say about space?

Space does not belong to the world of things-in-Space does not belong to the world of things-in-

themselves, but is contributed by our understanding themselves, but is contributed by our understanding ((VerstandVerstand))

Space is the form of intuition (Space is the form of intuition (AnschauungsformAnschauungsform) of outer ) of outer sense (

sense (Sinnlichkeit,Sinnlichkeit, sinnlighet) sinnlighet)

The axioms of Euclid are synthetic, but still necessaryThe axioms of Euclid are synthetic, but still necessary

They are necessary, because Euclidean space is a They are necessary, because Euclidean space is a necessary condition for all empirical knowledge necessary condition for all empirical knowledge

Spatial intuition is not itself a kind of knowledge. Neither Spatial intuition is not itself a kind of knowledge. Neither is it conceptual in nature, since it is prior to all concepts is it conceptual in nature, since it is prior to all concepts

as well as to knowledge. Neither is it an experience.

as well as to knowledge. Neither is it an experience.

(So what, then, (So what, then, is is spatial intuition?) spatial intuition?)

(4)

Which are the standard objections to Kant’s view?Which are the standard objections to Kant’s view?

 Kant’s theory makes him a subjectivist and idealist about

space because according to it, propositions concerning spatial relations are made true by facts about our own consciousness

 It also makes him anti-empirical, in the sense that putative a priori knowledge is allowed to override empirical evidence

 Kant did not recognize the existence of non-Euclidean geometries, or even their possibility

 The existence of consistent non-Euclidean geometries shows that Euclid’s axioms are not necessary

 Kant’s theory of space is not compatible with Einstein’s

theories of relativity, which offer the true story about space

 Kant’s theory makes him a subjectivist and idealist about

space because according to it, propositions concerning spatial relations are made true by facts about our own consciousness

 It also makes him anti-empirical, in the sense that putative a priori knowledge is allowed to override empirical evidence

 Kant did not recognize the existence of non-Euclidean geometries, or even their possibility

 The existence of consistent non-Euclidean geometries shows that Euclid’s axioms are not necessary

 Kant’s theory of space is not compatible with Einstein’s

theories of relativity, which offer the true story about space

(5)

Why are the standard objections wrong, 1:

Did Kant exclude other geometries than that of Euclid?

Why are the standard objections wrong, 1:

Did Kant exclude other geometries than that of Euclid?

By classifying our knowledge of Euclidean geometry as

synthetic apriori knowledge, Kant excluded the possibility that Euclidean geometry is true on logical or conceptual grounds

In other words, Kant did not hold that the axioms of Euclid are logically or semantically necessary

Hence, Kant’s theory does allow for the logical and conceptual possibility of non-Euclidean geometries

By the same token, the existence of consistent non-Euclidean geometries does not show that Kant was wrong in saying that the axioms of Euclid are necessary (in his sense of that term)

By classifying our knowledge of Euclidean geometry as

synthetic apriori knowledge, Kant excluded the possibility that Euclidean geometry is true on logical or conceptual grounds

In other words, Kant did not hold that the axioms of Euclid are logically or semantically necessary

Hence, Kant’s theory does allow for the logical and conceptual possibility of non-Euclidean geometries

By the same token, the existence of consistent non-Euclidean geometries does not show that Kant was wrong in saying that the axioms of Euclid are necessary (in his sense of that term)

(6)

Why are the standard objections wrong, 2:

The subjectivity of space

Why are the standard objections wrong, 2:

The subjectivity of space

 Kant’s empiricist adversaries (Reichenbach 1927, Nagel 1960) seem to agree with him on the subjectivity of space.

 Reichenbach argues that the Euclidean axioms are not the only ones that can be used to describe physical space.

 He concludes that Kant is therefore wrong in holding that these axioms are necessary.

 But his argument involves admitting that Euclidian geometry is among the geometries that can be used to describe actual

physical space – even considering Einstein’s discoveries

 Reichenbach and Nagel also hold that the choice between geometries is a matter of convenience.

 The physical laws get much more complicated if you choose the Euclidean alternative, but physics does not contradict Euclid.

 Hence, choosing an Euclidean geometry would not mean letting apriori propositions override empirical observations

 Kant’s empiricist adversaries (Reichenbach 1927, Nagel 1960) seem to agree with him on the subjectivity of space.

 Reichenbach argues that the Euclidean axioms are not the only ones that can be used to describe physical space.

 He concludes that Kant is therefore wrong in holding that these axioms are necessary.

 But his argument involves admitting that Euclidian geometry is among the geometries that can be used to describe actual

physical space – even considering Einstein’s discoveries

 Reichenbach and Nagel also hold that the choice between geometries is a matter of convenience.

 The physical laws get much more complicated if you choose the Euclidean alternative, but physics does not contradict Euclid.

 Hence, choosing an Euclidean geometry would not mean letting apriori propositions override empirical observations

(7)

Choosing between geometriesChoosing between geometries

• When light from a distant star passes near a celestial body with a considerable mass (such as the sun), it seems to bend

• I say ”seems to bend”, since contemporary physics instead says that the light rays follow straight lines, but space is curved.

• But the popular way of describing the situation is not wrong, only inconvenient for the physicist (since it involves postulating a universal force acting at a distance: gravitation).

• None of the alternative geometries is the ”true” system.

• When light from a distant star passes near a celestial body with a considerable mass (such as the sun), it seems to bend

• I say ”seems to bend”, since contemporary physics instead says that the light rays follow straight lines, but space is curved.

• But the popular way of describing the situation is not wrong, only inconvenient for the physicist (since it involves postulating a universal force acting at a distance: gravitation).

• None of the alternative geometries is the ”true” system.

(8)

How to handle bent light (a.k.a. curved space)How to handle bent light (a.k.a. curved space)

 Don’t bother about

Einstein, but take out a course towards where you know the star is (1), and go to warp speed!

 A more mundane example: consider a

heron that must catch a fish in spite of the light being bent at the surface.

Staying with an Euclidean geometry means aiming directly at the place

where it knows that the fish is located.

 Don’t bother about

Einstein, but take out a course towards where you know the star is (1), and go to warp speed!

 A more mundane example: consider a

heron that must catch a fish in spite of the light being bent at the surface.

Staying with an Euclidean geometry means aiming directly at the place

where it knows that the fish is located.

(9)

What does it mean to ”use” a geometry?

(Or: what is spatial intuition?)

What does it mean to ”use” a geometry?

(Or: what is spatial intuition?)

 Geometrical statements have an empirical meaning only in combination with coordinative definitions (Reichenbach)

 In physics, the coordinative definition of length is in terms of rigid bodies that are assumed not to change length when transported

 An empirical geometry can also be determined by general constraints such as the non-existence of universal forces ( space is curved)

 Or by the conditions that certain geometrical statements, for example those of Euclid, shall hold ( space is not curved)

 But in the latter case, are there any corresponding coordinative definitions? If not, ”Euclid’s geometry holds” is empirically empty

 In my interpretation, spatial intuition offers the needed definitions, and therebye ties geometry to experience

 Spatial intuition should be identified with personal action space

 Spatial intuition is not specifically tied to vision, and the translation of Anschauungsform as ”visualisation” (Reichenbach) is extremely misleading. ((For a similar confusion cf. the term ”visuospatial”.))

 Geometrical statements have an empirical meaning only in combination with coordinative definitions (Reichenbach)

 In physics, the coordinative definition of length is in terms of rigid bodies that are assumed not to change length when transported

 An empirical geometry can also be determined by general constraints such as the non-existence of universal forces ( space is curved)

 Or by the conditions that certain geometrical statements, for example those of Euclid, shall hold ( space is not curved)

 But in the latter case, are there any corresponding coordinative definitions? If not, ”Euclid’s geometry holds” is empirically empty

 In my interpretation, spatial intuition offers the needed definitions, and therebye ties geometry to experience

 Spatial intuition should be identified with personal action space

 Spatial intuition is not specifically tied to vision, and the translation of Anschauungsform as ”visualisation” (Reichenbach) is extremely misleading. ((For a similar confusion cf. the term ”visuospatial”.))

(10)

Why Euclidean space is a necessary condition for all empirical knowledge (1)

Why Euclidean space is a necessary condition for all empirical knowledge (1)

 All empirical knowledge is ultimately based on direct observation

 If a direct observation gives rise to the hypothesis that the object a has property P, this hypothesis can be verified by observation only if one can re-identify a

 More generally, for an observation of a to give knowledge that a is P, as distinct from that b is P, c is P etc., one must know that what one observes is a, and is not b, c etc.

 If a direct observation gives rise to the hypothesis that the object a has property P, and no property of a except its location is known, this hypothesis can be verified by another observation only if one can re-identify a by means of a direct identification of its spatio- temporal location. (In the following, ”temporal” is disregarded!)

 More generally, for an observation of a to give knowledge that a is P, as distinct from that b is P, c is P etc., when none of a:s properties except its location are known, one must identify a as a by means of a direct identification of its spatial location.

 All empirical knowledge is ultimately based on direct observation

 If a direct observation gives rise to the hypothesis that the object a has property P, this hypothesis can be verified by observation only if one can re-identify a

 More generally, for an observation of a to give knowledge that a is P, as distinct from that b is P, c is P etc., one must know that what one observes is a, and is not b, c etc.

 If a direct observation gives rise to the hypothesis that the object a has property P, and no property of a except its location is known, this hypothesis can be verified by another observation only if one can re-identify a by means of a direct identification of its spatio- temporal location. (In the following, ”temporal” is disregarded!)

 More generally, for an observation of a to give knowledge that a is P, as distinct from that b is P, c is P etc., when none of a:s properties except its location are known, one must identify a as a by means of a direct identification of its spatial location.

(11)

The nature of spatial intuition The nature of spatial intuition

 Human beings (and many other animals) have an inbuilt very reliable spatial metric for length and angle that is independent of sensory input, and that can therefore be used to re-identify objects

independently of their non-spatial properties

 This metric is used when we perform so-called ”ballistic” and ”semi- ballistic” movements. Example: the fast grabbing of an object on the other side of a fragile vase, with eyes shut. (And the heron’s strike.)

 Suppose, for simplicity’s sake, that in any situation we can either take a step forwards, or turn 90 degrees either clockwise or anti- clockwise. The step length is changeable at will, but fixed in the sense of being pre-determined for each occurrence of a movement.

Further, we keep track of our movements for a long time.

 Using the supposed capacities, we can knowingly re-visit all places that we have visited lately (= not too late for our memory span)

 Hence we can re-identify all objects that we have observed during this time, without relying on any non-spatial properties

 Human beings (and many other animals) have an inbuilt very reliable spatial metric for length and angle that is independent of sensory input, and that can therefore be used to re-identify objects

independently of their non-spatial properties

 This metric is used when we perform so-called ”ballistic” and ”semi- ballistic” movements. Example: the fast grabbing of an object on the other side of a fragile vase, with eyes shut. (And the heron’s strike.)

 Suppose, for simplicity’s sake, that in any situation we can either take a step forwards, or turn 90 degrees either clockwise or anti- clockwise. The step length is changeable at will, but fixed in the sense of being pre-determined for each occurrence of a movement.

Further, we keep track of our movements for a long time.

 Using the supposed capacities, we can knowingly re-visit all places that we have visited lately (= not too late for our memory span)

 Hence we can re-identify all objects that we have observed during this time, without relying on any non-spatial properties

(12)

Why Euclidean space is a necessary condition for all empirical knowledge (3)

Why Euclidean space is a necessary condition for all empirical knowledge (3)

 Re-visiting a point via a detour in non-Euclidean space using a fixed angle of the turns (such as 90 degrees) will not work, because the angles of the composite path that you walk will not sum up to the intended result.

 In a spherical geometry with constant curvature, the angles will be too small.

 The walk will be even more problematic in a geometry with irregular ”bumps” and ”sinks”.

 Re-visiting a point via a detour in non-Euclidean space using a fixed angle of the turns (such as 90 degrees) will not work, because the angles of the composite path that you walk will not sum up to the intended result.

 In a spherical geometry with constant curvature, the angles will be too small.

 The walk will be even more problematic in a geometry with irregular ”bumps” and ”sinks”.

Source: Wikimedia Commons

(13)

What I have not said What I have not said

 My argument is not the common one that we can use Euclidean geometry for object re-identification in everyday life, because the actual curvature of close space is negligible and the

Euclidean system therefore a good approximation of the truth.

This is not my argument because

 1) there is no true geometrical system and therefore no

”actual” curvature, and

 2) the Euclidean system can be used even in regions of space that the non-Euclidean would describe as having a strong

curvature. All points in such a region can, in principle, be visited and re-visited using the proposed inbuilt ability.

 Another mundane example. Suppose that you want to leave a hall of mirrors through its only door as fast as possible, in spite of a lot of confusing mirror images suggesting an irregularly curved space. If you remember how you walked from the door to where you are, you can simply close your eyes and go back to the door without caring about the non-Euclidic suggestions.

 My argument is not the common one that we can use Euclidean geometry for object re-identification in everyday life, because the actual curvature of close space is negligible and the

Euclidean system therefore a good approximation of the truth.

This is not my argument because

 1) there is no true geometrical system and therefore no

”actual” curvature, and

 2) the Euclidean system can be used even in regions of space that the non-Euclidean would describe as having a strong

curvature. All points in such a region can, in principle, be visited and re-visited using the proposed inbuilt ability.

 Another mundane example. Suppose that you want to leave a hall of mirrors through its only door as fast as possible, in spite of a lot of confusing mirror images suggesting an irregularly curved space. If you remember how you walked from the door to where you are, you can simply close your eyes and go back to the door without caring about the non-Euclidic suggestions.

(14)

The nature of the synthetic a prioriThe nature of the synthetic a priori

 Euclid’s geometry is not a theory that is true or false because the world is the way it is, but a framework for describing the world that we use because it fits our epistemic purposes

 Neither are the propositions of Euclid analytical statements about the relations between axioms and theorems

 So they do not describe anything factual, nor anything logical

 Instead they express

 1) our fundamental choice of framework and

 2) logical consequences of that choice that we must, consequentially, adapt to

 In other words, they do not state any Laws of Nature, but formulate our own Laws for describing Nature.

 The statements of Euclid’s geometry are normative in nature.

 In this, they are like all other statements of applied mathematics.

 Euclid’s geometry is not a theory that is true or false because the world is the way it is, but a framework for describing the world that we use because it fits our epistemic purposes

 Neither are the propositions of Euclid analytical statements about the relations between axioms and theorems

 So they do not describe anything factual, nor anything logical

 Instead they express

 1) our fundamental choice of framework and

 2) logical consequences of that choice that we must, consequentially, adapt to

 In other words, they do not state any Laws of Nature, but formulate our own Laws for describing Nature.

 The statements of Euclid’s geometry are normative in nature.

 In this, they are like all other statements of applied mathematics.

(15)

Thank you for your attentionThank you for your attention1,2,3,41,2,3,4!!

1) Note that attention is an internalised version of a prototypical ballistic reach for an object.

2) Note that Euclid held an emission theory of vision.

3) Many thanks also to all who commented on earlier versions of this text. You will be given full credit in the definitive version of the paper.

4) (Note added in March 2020) A few very minor edits have been performed on pp.

8 and 12 to fix two copyright issues and to improve clarity.

1) Note that attention is an internalised version of a prototypical ballistic reach for an object.

2) Note that Euclid held an emission theory of vision.

3) Many thanks also to all who commented on earlier versions of this text. You will be given full credit in the definitive version of the paper.

4) (Note added in March 2020) A few very minor edits have been performed on pp.

8 and 12 to fix two copyright issues and to improve clarity.

References

Related documents

They divided the 53 students into three groups, the different groups were given: feedback with a sit-down with a teacher for revision and time for clarification, direct written

In this thesis we investigated the Internet and social media usage for the truck drivers and owners in Bulgaria, Romania, Turkey and Ukraine, with a special focus on

Sekventiell samverkan kännetecknas av en stegvis arbetsprocess där varje medarbetare väntar på sin tur att utföra sin uppgift för att sedan lämna över nästa moment

For future reference, free seedlings and the carbon payments will be defined as a decrease in investment cost and increased labor costs and reduced rainfall as reductions

En känsla av kvinnlig underkastelse framkom då många kvinnor, enligt deltagarna, vet vad ingreppet går ut på men ändå inte har förmågan, eller möjligheten, att sätta sin

89 www.hrw.org Divorced from Justice, s. 90 www.hrw.org Divorced from Justice, s. 91 www.hrw.org Divorced from Justice, s.. skilsmässa på grund av makens impotens dröja upp till

vandrar normalt mellan vinter och sommarbeten vilket ofta blir mellan inland och kust längs norrlandskusten (Sweanor m.fl. 1989) och den vandringen kan bli avbruten av en barriär som

To answer the question as to “Which types of pre-birth genetic modification are acceptable from the perspective of Kant’s ethics theory?” we have to look at what Kant’s idea was