• No results found

Democracy and future generations

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "Democracy and future generations"

Copied!
3
0
0

Loading.... (view fulltext now)

Full text

(1)

http://www.diva-portal.org

Postprint

This is the accepted version of a paper presented at Trondheim 2005.

Citation for the original published paper:

Bergström, L. (2005)

Democracy and future generations.

In: Democracy unbound/Basic explorations: Stockholm studies in democratic theory, vol. 1 (pp.

192-).

N.B. When citing this work, cite the original published paper.

Permanent link to this version:

http://urn.kb.se/resolve?urn=urn:nbn:se:su:diva-20367

(2)

Printed in: Democracy Unbound: Basic Explorations, Stockholm Studies in Democratic Theory, Vol. I, Stockholm University, 2005, pp. 190-192.

Democracy and future generations

Lars Bergström Stockholm University

A main virtue of democracy is that those who are affected by a political decision have a chance of taking part in the political process leading up to that decision. Another virtue is that those who are affected by a decision can vote the decision-makers out of office in the next election, if they are dissatisfied with the decision.

However, these virtues of democracy can only be realized to some limited extent. For example, future people are often affected by current political decisions, but they cannot take part in those decisions, since they are not yet born. Again, future people cannot punish obnoxious decision-makers, who have harmed their interests but are no longer alive.

Does this show that democracy is impossible? Or is there a way in which the interests or preferences of future people can be made to influence current decisions?

One idea is that future people can be represented by some currently living person (ombudsman) or persons (party). Of course, there are problems with this, since it may be hard to find out what future people will want before they are able to express their preferences. But to some extent, we have this problem already with living people, since they may not have expressed their preferences on a lot of issues that have to be settled by their representatives. In both cases, the representatives may nevertheless be able to make reasonable estimates of what the relevant interests are. Besides, even in current decision-making, politicians claim to be able to take the interests of future people into account. I think this is generally believed to be possible. The problem is rather that current politicians may not give sufficient weight to the interests of future generations; that is why special representatives of those generations may be needed.

However, if democrats should modify existing political institutions in order to satisfy future interests in a more efficient way, should they not also make it possible for the interests of past people to influence current decisions? Present political systems may have a bias towards the present, but if they are replaced by systems that give a greater weight to future interests while ignoring past interests, we seem to get a bias towards the future as a result. If we want to stick to the ideals of “one person, one vote” and “each to count for one and no one for more than one”, it seems that we should not favor the future at the expense of the past. So, we should make room for past people to influence our decisions.

I guess some people may think that this is a crazy idea. But why is it crazy? A tempting answer is that past people are not affected by our decisions, since they are dead, while future people may still live to suffer the consequences. I admit that there is some truth in this.

Nevertheless, it is not a conclusive objection. For people do have preferences – sometimes very strong preferences – concerning what will happen when they are dead. For example, people tend to care about what happens to their grand-children and great-grand-children. We also tend to care about the future of the world and the environment. And, in particular, we think that our own preferences for various possible future states of the world can and should influence our present decisions, even if we ourselves will no longer be around when those future states are realized. We think that we have a right to make decisions which have

(3)

consequences in the far future (and which may not have any important consequences before we die). So how can we deny the same right to past people?

If my reasoning so far is correct, we may take one further step. If other generations than our own have a right to influence our decisions, we should perhaps give up our bias towards the present altogether. This means, I suppose, that even with respect to our own decisions, each generation should count as one and no one as more than one. A consequence of this would be that our own generation – i.e. people who have a democratic right to vote now – should have almost no influence at all over our decisions. This seems to be the opposite of democracy. So maybe a democrat should conclude that other generations should have no influence over our decisions. In particular, then, future people should not be allowed to take any part in current decision-making. This makes our life so much simpler. Hence, better.

However, this move seems to be clearly undemocratic in the sense that it abandons the central idea that those affected by a decision should be able to influence it, at least indirectly.

The bias towards the present is indeed a bias.

Could the bias be justified by a principle of proportionality, to the effect that a persons degree of influence over a decision should be proportional to the degree to which he or she is influenced by it? I do not think so. This principle cannot be satisfied, since our decisions frequently do have a bearing on the interests of past and future people. Indeed, some of our decisions may affect future generations much more than the affect us.

Besides, a principle of proportionality may have consequences for our present generation that are somewhat disagreeable. In some respects, its consequences are probably very good, but do we also willing to restrict the voting power of the elderly on the ground that they will not be affected by our decisions for very long? The subsidiarity principle of the European Union is attractive, but this is mainly concerned with geographical distances. It distinguishes between union, national, regional and local levels. But as far as I know it ignores temporal distances. A temporal subsidiarity principle, on the other hand, seems to have a clear bias towards the young. Do we really want to accept that? And if we do not, should we then reject the ordinary subsidiarity principle as well? For the sake of consistency?

References

Related documents

Despite the low annual volume, there are now clear signals that a recovery is un- derway. Transaction volumes have picked up significantly in the last two quarters, foreign

I have introduced the research questions that are the red thread throughout this thesis and made clear that I analyse the discourses of the employees at the

(Slowness is luxury. This proposal encourages you to take your time and experience processes. Enjoy the attention and care. And through this, celebrate everyday experiences and

Let me conclude by saying that entrepreneurs who will be able to design that to be lived new journey, will not only be part of that cultural transformation that is already

This dissertation concludes that the EUNIC clusters do not provide (international) cultural relations with a European added value and that this will not change until the

Shows the structure of a housing area with private (front yard), semi private (communal space in a housing cluster), semi public (pocket park within a block), and public

A general overview of the main aspects of spin-polaron theory are given in Chapter 4, while in Chapter 5, we discuss methods and ap- proaches of the density functional theory (DFT)

Accordingly, this paper aims to investigate how three companies operating in the food industry; Max Hamburgare, Innocent and Saltå Kvarn, work with CSR and how this work has